CAIRN-INT.INFO : International Edition

1Recent studies have discussed some of the “chronic” difficulties of our discipline. There have been critiques of the sometimes radical split between theory and research (Boudon, 1997; Cuin, 2000; Goldthorpe, 1997,2000c; Hedstrom and Swedberg, 1996,1998b); the weakness of sociological theory has been highlighted (Coleman, 1990; Van den Berg, 1998); questions have been raised about the foundations of empirical research (Ragin and Becker, 1992) and the scientific status of sociological analysis altogether (Cuin, 2000, 2004; Passeron, 1991; Raynaud, 2006). The exchange between Raymond Boudon (2002c) and John Goldthorpe (2004) around “sociology that matters” represents a meaningful synthesis of this “reflexive effervescence” in contemporary sociology.

2This article originates from similar methodological concerns, though it bears not on sociology in general but a specific research tradition, “empirical quantitative sociology”. [1]

3This particular current of sociological analysis has been the focus of lively critical debate aimed at getting beyond certain fundamental limitations. The fact that such important works as Stanley Lieberson’s (1985), Charles Ragin’s (1987) or Ray Pawson’s (1989) did not suffice to curb the potential “dangers” due to naive use of techniques that were becoming increasingly sophisticated is clearly visible in the virulent renewal of the debate in the 1990s (Clogg and Haritou, 1997; Esser, 1996; Sociological Methodology, 1991,21, pp. 291-358; Sorenson, 1998). These critical discussions began generating precise methodological proposals for improving the situation. To increase the microfoundation of empirical quantitative sociology, Hans-Peter Blossfeld (1996, 1998) recommended extending the use and analysis of longitudinal quantitative data by means of “event history analysis” techniques; Andrew Abbott (1992a, 1992b, 1995,2000; Abbott and Hrycak, 1990; Abbott and Tsay, 2000) proposed applying the notion of “narrative” using the technique of “optimal matching analysis” originating in biology; Peter Abell (1984,1998, 2003) agreed with the idea of substituting the notion of “narrative” for “variable” (see also Abell, 2004) but in contrast to Abbott, proposed an algebraic rather than metric implementation method. [2]

4This article analyzes the recent literature that has been fueling the debate on the limitations of empirical quantitative sociology, literature which offers clear indications of a way of reformulating that approach which would extend its explanatory power. The focus here is on four types of scientific contributions : 1) those that discuss problems specific to this approach; 2) those related to the notions of social action and rationality; 3) studies of the concept of generative mechanisms; 4) publications on applying simulation methods in sociology. It may be shown that these four types of sociological production refer back to each other. My research suggests that the intersection of the four constitutes a methodological project that reformulates empirical quantitative sociology.

5To anticipate the conclusions reached, it can be said that the last three areas of the debate provide general solutions to the problems raised by the first. In other words, recent literature has begun to outline a type of empirical quantitative sociology wherein variable analysis describes, mechanism modeling (where mechanisms are built in non-reductionist methodological individualism terms) explains, and simulation activates and runs (as well as tests) the mechanisms assumed to be the basis for observed statistical relations. I am well aware that, thus formulated, this idea is supported by only a limited part of the literature; what’s more, certain aspects of these debates–above all the material on “social simulation”– are unfamiliar to most sociologists. The view advanced here is nonetheless supported by the few articles in which the connections discussed are explicitly brought together (see Edling, 2002; Fararo, 1997; Fararo and Butts, 1999; Goldthorpe, 1999; Hedstrom, 2005, ch. 6; Hummon and Fararo, 1995).

6Clearly, then, this article is concerned with the debate “inside” the quantitative approach, fueled by researchers not hostile to that approach and who recommend amending rather than abandoning it. This choice seems justifiable. As Ray Pawson points out (1989, ch. 1), many of the attacks on this approach amount to no more than a means for the critics to forge their own sociological identity, and the criticisms have not been followed by constructive proposals. The clearest manifestation of this attitude is found among the so-called “interpretive” sociologists (see, for example, Berger, 2002 and Blumer, 1956). [3] However, the choice may produce an equivocation; i.e., it might give the reader a dichotomous vision of the contemporary epistemological and methodological debate, suggesting that there are “interpretive” or “constructivist” types of sociology on the one hand, on the other quantitative approaches with “nomothetic” aims. Though I am aware of this ambiguity, I hope the plurality of authors and contributions discussed in this reconstruction will suffice to dispel any sense of equivocation or sterile opposition, which is far from my purposes here.

7The article is divided into three parts. The first concerns recent written discussion of the main limitations of variable analysis. Since this debate is more familiar than the others, only the essential components of it are presented. The second is concerned with how empirical quantitative sociology may benefit from being combined with an actionist perspective, an explanatory strategy based on generative mechanisms and simulation analysis. The third discusses a specific sociological area–the sociology of social mobility– where recent literature has been changing in major ways that suggest a reformulation and enriching of the “standard” quantitative approach. The analysis concludes by suggesting how close these contemporary debates are to older ideas and outlines a response to the question of why these ideas have only quite recently been fully received.

Three major problems with “variable analysis”

8Explanatory power has not kept pace with growing technical sophistication. The most attentive recent literature readily admits this major limitation in using multivariate statistical methods to analyze social phenomena (Freedman, 1991a, 1991b).

9Three groups of problems may be cited to account for this “structural discrepancy” specific to empirical quantitative sociology : 1) its a-theoreticalness; 2) its reductive conception of causation; 3) its merely partial handling of the multi-level aspect of social phenomena.

10“Quantitative sociology remains very theory-poor” (Sorensen, 1998, p. 238). Freedman (1991a) suggested that this feature affects several stages of quantitative research. The first is defining the model; i.e., the structure of relations among the variables to be tested (Goldthorpe, 1996a; Sorensen, 1998). [4] The second concerns the crucial moment of selecting and accepting the model. Many researchers have remarked that the choice of the “best model” (supposing it can be made at all) cannot be made on a purely statistical basis (Aish-Van Vaerenbergh, 1994, p. 115; Bohrnstedt and Knoke, 1998; Cobalti, 1992, p. 123; Cherkaoui, 2005, ch. 4; Wunsch, 1994, p. 37). Third, empirical quantitative sociology often underestimates the role of theory during analysis of “control variables”, either in choosing the variables to be inserted [5] or in interpreting the effects of the interactions brought to light (Sorensen, 1998). [6] Lastly, the justification of conditions (forms of variable distribution, error structure and relations among variables) that any “statistical model” must establish in order to be reasonably applied and correctly estimated also lacks theory (Freedman, 1991a). [7] The many statistical tests now available do not entirely resolve the problem : statistical justification and sociological justification do not necessarily coincide. This is particularly clear for one of the most generally assumed conditions of validity in empirical quantitative sociology, namely the linearity hypothesis (Clogg and Haritou, 1997, p. 88, p. 93; Abbott, 1992a, p. 433, p. 434), which is usually justified on the basis of the parcimony principle without specifying that that principle is often only computational, not sociological (Sorensen, 1998, p. 249). The a-theoreticalness of variable analysis also assumes another form. Ray Pawson (1989) stresses the lack of theoretical thinking in choosing and justifying measurement levels of inserted variables.

11The second aspect likely to be called into question is the concept of causation specific to empirical quantitative sociology. The logical core of multivariate analysis as conceptualized by Paul Lazarsfeld in the 1950s consisted in studying variations in the intensity of the tie between two variables, X and Y, produced by consecutive insertion of a series of additional variables Wn. A relatively high degree of association intensity stability is considered a sign that the variables Wn are acting neither as “intermediary” or “parasitic” variables. In empirical quantitative sociology, qualifying the link between X and Y as causal depends on this “control process”. Given the effects of Wn, if X —> Y “resists”, the hypothesis of mere correlation may be ruled out in favor of a causation hypothesis (Becker, 1992, p. 206; Ragin, 1987, pp. 58-61). This idea of “causation as robust dependence”, to use John Goldthorpe’s expression (1999, pp. 138-142; see also Hedstrom, 2003), has one major limitation, however. In contrast to experimental control based on randomly assigning cases to groups, the “statistical control” procedure does not ensure that all variables susceptible of influencing dependent variable Y are taken into account (Lieberson, 1985 [8], ch. 2 and 6; Ragin, 1987, pp. 61-67). Clogg and Haritou (1997) recently drew all the relevant conclusions from this observation. Because the hypothesis that relevant non-measured variables are not correlated with the independent variable cannot be tested using the data one is in the process of analyzing, no variant of the “generalized linear model” has anything to say about the causal aspect of the relations studied. [9]

12Once this major problem has been acknowledged, the image of causation as “robust dependence” is seen to have three major limitations. First, it implies a “technicist” reduction of sociological explanation. The statistical control process may lead the researcher to identify the causal effects of a variable–and therefore its explanatory power– with the value of regression coefficients or more generally with one of the “goodness of fit” measures (Abell, 1984, p. 311; Clogg and Haritou, 1997, p. 92, pp. 93-94, p. 100; Freedman, 1991a; Sorensen, 1998, p. 241, p. 243). This same identification, probably coupled with a “determinist” conception of explanation, may then lead to the logical error of imputing causation to variables instead of actors. It is in this sense that Harmut Esser (1996, p. 160, p. 162, p. 164) qualifies “variable sociology” as “meaninglessness”: it lacks the dimension of the meaning of individual action and actors’ intentions. [10] Lastly, and contrary to what might be expected, multivariate analysis favors a “mono-dimensional” vision of causation to the detriment of a “pluri-dimensional or configurational” one. Some of the conditions necessary for estimating any variant of the generalized linear model require that independent variable effects be uniform regardless of the levels of the other variables; this amounts to hypothesizing causal effect independence (Becker, 1992, p. 207; Ragin, 1987, pp. 63-64). Though this is not impossible from a purely technical point of view, empirical variable sociology tends to underestimate the complex nature of causation; i.e., the multiple interactions among explanatory factors (Abbott, 1992a). [11]

13Empirical quantitative sociology’s handling of the micro-macro problem is the third main focus for criticism of this approach. There are two main difficulties to using multivariate statistical techniques in this connection. First, they may lead the researcher to identify the aggregate level of analysis with the macro level, which amounts to reducing transition modes from the individual level to the macro-social level to nothing more than the “simple process” of aggregating individual actions using a logical operation of the “juxtaposition of analytic units” sort. Empirical quantitative sociology thus tends to neglect another, sociologically essential means of composing individual actions, namely the “complex aggregation mechanisms” involving interdependence of analytic units (Abbott, 1992a, p. 431, p. 434; Cherkaoui, 2005, ch. 2,3,6; Cuin, 2002; Esser, 1996, pp. 160-162; Hedstrom, 2003; Hedstrom and Swedberg, 1996, p. 136). [12] The second difficulty of this approach with respect to the micro-macro link has to do the fact that there is no change in level of analysis when it comes to interpreting the variable relation structure brought to light. Arthur Stinchcombe (1991, pp. 370-371) insisted that the process of inserting control variables–the core of statistical explanation– remains at the aggregated level. This means that no true understanding of the micro-individual processes responsible for the emersion of this or that structure of relations is possible. [13]

14A variety of ways of underestimating theory, a reductive conception of causation, incomplete handling of the micro-macro problem–these are the major problems that a significant segment of recent literature imputes to empirical quantitative sociology. What is to be done ? For Blalock (1991, p. 333) the answer is to increase the complexity of models while continuously subjecting their conditions of validity and theoretical implications to critical examination and debate. Freedman’s answer to this is : “If I am right, playing the game harder will not help. It is the rules that we need to change” (1991b, p. 357).

15The analysis of recent literature presented in the following section shows that the most careful empirical quantitative sociology is starting to move in the second of these directions.

Three possible types of integration

The “language of variables” and the “language of action”

16One of the richest debates in contemporary sociology concerns the form and place that a theory of action should have in sociological analysis (Marini, 1992; Déchaux, 2002). Though rational choice theory appears to be at the core of these discussions, [14] it is in fact only one aspect of the new interest in action, the actor and rationality. The thinking of Siegwart Lindenberg on the “method of decreasing abstraction” (Lindenberg, 1992,2003, p. 362) and the “principle of sufficient complexity” (2002,2003, p. 362) suggests in fact that rational choice theory can be no more than the point of departure for constructing a theory of action in sociology. The simplifications effected by this theory have non-negligeable consequences on our way of conceiving and constructing the phenomenon to be explained (Lindenberg, 1998). The aim of many of Raymond Boudon’s works (1989,1993,1995,1996,1998,1999, 2001,2002a, 2002b, 2003) has been to show that this conception of intentional rational action could be fitted into a more general analytic framework identifiable as a type of methodological individualism that does not reduce actors’ rationality to mere instrumental or consequentialist rationality. Lindenberg’s discussion of Boudon’s cognitive rationality model is evidence that the honing of a “social” understanding of rationality has been one of the richest developments in this debate (Lindenberg, 2000; see also the exchange between Cuin [2005] and Boudon [2005a]).

17The fact is that whatever variant of rational choice theory or methodological individualism one decides to adopt, [15] the shared hypothesis of an idealtypical intentional and rational actor has great methodological appeal.

18In this connection two essential points should be noted. [16] First, this hypothesis presents an “explanatory plus” in that no supplementary condition is required once it has been established that the phenomenon to be explained results from a composition of individual intentional, rational actions (Coleman, 1986b, p. 1). This frees explanation of all black boxes (Boudon, 1998). Indeed, we can only observe that there can be no source of causation other than individual action and the reasons that inspire it, norms being only a parameter of action, not its determinant (Hedstrom and Swedberg, 1998b, pp. 11-13). Second, the reference to rational individual action plays a major role in conceptualizing the micro-macro problem (Abell, 1992; Cherkaoui, 2005, ch. 2; Friedman and Hechter, 1988; Hedstrom and Swedberg, 1996). In this respect, the actor and his/her reasons may be understood to constitute the essential link in the following sequence : “structure” —> “interaction” —> “action” —> “interaction” —> “structure”.

FIGURE I.

Coleman-Boudon Diagram

FIGURE I.
FIGURE I. – Coleman-Boudon Diagram Macro (structure) <--------> Macro (structure) [Interaction] [Interaction] Micro (action)

Coleman-Boudon Diagram

19James Coleman explicitly formalized this schema (1986a, p. 1322,1990, ch. 1). It is also present in many of Raymond Boudon’s works (1977b, 1984, 1986,2002b). [17] Peter Abell (2003) has recently taken it up, somewhat amended it and discussed it at length. This conception of sociological explanation has been termed “structural individualism” (Lindenberg, 1977; Wippler, 1978,1985; Raub, 1982; Udehn, 2001, ch. 10,2002 : 500; see also Manzo, 2007a).

20The qualifier “structural” is essential. It means that reference to the actor does not lead to a mistaken identification between micro-foundation and micro-reduction. The presence of the term “interaction” suggests that this can be avoided by taking into account the different types of interdependence structures in which actors are involved and that shape their ways of thinking as well as how their actions are conceived (Barbera, 2004, pp. 8-11, ch. 5). It is indeed interdependence structures that constitute the core of the passage from micro to macro. A genuine multilevel vision of social reality thus seems increasingly acceptable to contemporary sociologists. The “neo-structural sociology” current derived from the innovative work of Harrison White (Edling, 2002, pp. 206-208; Fararo, 1997, p. 79) seems particularly well equipped for studying and modeling this meso level because of this tradition’s particular attentiveness to social networks (Lazega and Favereau, 2002, pp. 2-11; Lazega, 2003). [18]

21What does this type of debate mean for critical analysis of empirical quantitative sociology ?

22Taking into account the above individualist (but non-reductionist) conception of explanation when doing variable analysis would have three beneficial effects in connection with the problems just brought to light. First, focusing on actors’ intentional and rational actions would be a powerful means of bringing theory back into the research process since it is clearly the researcher’s theoretical, hypothetical reasoning that would produce a representation of the link between structure, action and statistical regularities. Second, the reference to individual action means that researchers could not proceed by attributing causation to variables and their reciprocal effects. Causation would be formulated in terms of actors, intentional actions and the interdependence among those actions. Lastly, the multilevel nature of this form of actionism would force the researcher to move from the aggregated or macro level that the statistical analysis is situated at and pay attention to the way individual actions and combinations of them could have engendered the regularities brought to light by multivariate analysis.

23It must be noted that empirical quantitative sociology has begun to accept these arguments. In 1996, John Goldthorpe devoted an entire article to discussing the following thesis : “QAD clearly does need to be informed by some explicit theory of action, at all events where it is used with more than purely descriptive ambitions; and RAT [...] would appear distinctively suited to providing accounts of the generation of the probabilistic regularities, often extensive in time and space, that QAD has the capacity to reveal.” (1996a, p. 113). [19] In 1998, Hans-Peter Blossfeld and Gerald Prein edited a collective work devoted to this same argument. Each of the contributors expressed awareness of the necessity to link empirical quantitative sociology and action theory. [20]

24Though these ideas are certainly not shared by all, as Goldthorpe himself realistically admits (2000a, p. 20), the first move has been made. Combining “variables language” and “action language” is one way of improving empirical quantitative sociology.

The “language of variables” and the “language of mechanisms”

25The second contemporary sociology debate that must be taken into consideration bears on the notion of generative mechanism (see Cherkaoui, 2005). In particularly systematic works on this argument, the approach in which this notion is the essential methodological core of both theorizing and empirical research is called “analytic sociology” (Barbera, 2003,2004; Hedstrom, 2005). [21]

26The concept of generative mechanism is based on the idea of “generativity” (Fararo 1989, pp. 39-43; Fararo and Butts, 1999, p. 60). Attention is focused on the emergence, engendering or genesis of what is observed. Attending to the mechanism means attending to the “mode of production of phenomena” (Cherkaoui, 1998, ch. 3,2005, ch. 4). The postulate is the same regardless of whether mechanisms are conceived of as real entities in the world (Harré, 1972; Bunge, 1997; Fararo, 1989) or as analytic constructs (Stinchcombe, 1991; Hedstrom and Swedberg, 1998b): what is observed at “level K” must be explicable as an effect of one or several mechanisms positioned at “level K minus N”. For Y and X phenomena, whatever they may be, Figure II specifies that a mechanism is active in the emergence process of the relation as it is –namely its shape and nature– rather than on the values or behavior of variables considered separately. In other words, it would be inaccurate to conceptualize a mechanism as the equivalent of an intermediary or parasitic variable (Pawson, 1989, pp. 130-131).

FIGURE II.

Generative mechanisms and levels of reality

FIGURE II.
FIGURE II. – Generative mechanisms and levels of reality (“Level K”) Y < > X (Level of observation, description) “producing” or “engendering” relation (“Level K-N”) MECHANISM (Level of modeling and explanation)

Generative mechanisms and levels of reality

27In functional terms, a mechanism–or a chain of mechanisms (Gambetta, 1998)– answers the need to know how and why a relation–or a structure of relations– was engendered (Harré, 1972, p. 6, p. 118; Hedstrom, 2003).

28In substantive terms, on the other hand, a mechanism is nothing other than a theoretical model constructed in terms of individual actions and interactions (Cherkaoui, 1998, ch. 3,2005, ch. 4; Gambetta, 1998, p. 105; Hedstrom and Swedberg, 1998b, pp. 24-25; Schelling, 1998). But this individualist foundation should not be interpreted in reductionist terms (Bunge, 1997, p. 440, p. 441, p. 448, pp. 454-455, p. 457). All explanations in terms of mechanisms must work by way of three types of interdependent mechanisms : 1) “situational mechanisms” or “macro-micro mechanisms”, which model the structural components of social action; 2) “action formation mechanisms” or “micro-micro mechanisms”, aimed at modeling individual actors’ beliefs and ends; 3) “transformational mechanisms” or “micro-macro mechanisms” concerned with the process of simple or complex combining of individual actions (Hedstrom and Swedberg, 1998b, pp. 21-24). These concepts make it possible to insert the Coleman-Boudon schema (Figure I) into a more general analytic framework. Explanation by way of mechanisms implies “structural individualism” [22] (see also Manzo, 2007a).

29On these bases, advocates of the mechanism notion put forward the following major proposition : there can only be explanation, and therefore even more clearly causal explanation, on condition of modeling the mechanisms that underlie the observed relations (Blossfeld, 1996; Bunge, 1997, 1998; Elster, 1998,2003; Fararo, 1989; Hedstrom and Swedberg, 1998b; Pawson, 1989; Sorensen, 1998; Stinchcombe, 1991). Neither X’s temporal (or logical) precedence to Y nor observation of a systematic and recurrent link between them can justify attributing causation to that connection. It is the presence of a mechanism that accounts for the production of Y on the basis of the existence of X. This is what Harré (1972, p. 116, p. 121, pp. 136-137) defined as a “generative theory of causality”, in diametrical opposition to a “successionist theory of causality”. [23]

30Recent literature stresses that this kind of methodological position has obvious implications for empirical quantitative sociology.

31Explanation by generative mechanisms disqualifies the causal claims of variable-centered statistical explanation in that the parameters of a “statistical model” only express the intensity and the sign of the tie between Y and X without saying anything about the mechanisms responsible for producing it (Bunge, 1997; Harré, 1972; Hedstrom and Swedberg, 1998b, pp. 9-10, pp. 15-17; Cherkaoui, 2005, ch. 2; Elster, 1998,2003). The corollary cannot be neglected either : the explanatory ambition of variable analysis gets significantly downsized, and its role in the quantitative research process comes to be understood as no more than descriptive (Goldthorpe, 1999; Hedstrom, 2003; Hedstrom and Swedberg, 1998b). [24]

32Does this disqualify empirical quantitative sociology ? Hardly. The language of variables can synergize very well with reasoning in terms of mechanisms. First, this combination would bring theoretical thinking back to the fore because, given that mechanisms are not observable, they have to be theoretically modeled. Second, the partial, reductive conception of causation specific to variable analysis would be corrected in that the notion of mechanism prevents the researcher from identifying the “statistical significance” of parameters with sociologically significant relational causation. Lastly, modeling generative mechanisms would force researchers to position themselves in a multilevel analytic framework aimed at systematically relating the individual action (micro level), the interdependence structures existing between those actions (meso level) and the products emerging from the later in terms of institutions, norms and conventions (macro level).

33This is precisely the type of virtuous combination of variables and mechanisms that is explicitly proposed and discussed at length by John Goldthorpe in an article that, with a few exceptions (Barbera, 2004, ch. 7; Grusky and Di Carlo, 2001), has not received the attention I believe it deserves. “Causation, statistics, and sociology” (1999) represents a genuine manifesto for reformulating empirical quantitative sociology. [25] The English sociologist here sketches out an “alternative for sociology” in which the set of statistical tools would be used to bring to light empirical regularities while modeling of generative mechanisms would explain the emergence of those regularities. Goldthorpe explicitly endorses a “causation as generative process” view in which, once empirical regularities have been established, the point is to “hypothesiz[e] generative processes at the level of social action” (ibid., p. 151, pp. 154-155).

34Goldthorpe thus explicitly relates three objects : critical discussion of empirical quantitative sociology, methodological individualism, and generative mechanisms strategy. His ideas leave no doubt about the possibility of enriching empirical quantitative sociology by means of 1) an actionist viewpoint, 2) reasoning in terms of mechanisms.

The “language of variables” and simulation methods

35Since a phenomenon can be broken down into n variables, multivariate statistical techniques represent a powerful tool for formally describing the structure of relations existing between them. But how may the reasoning in terms of mechanisms required to explain the genesis of such a structure be made operative ? The literature on social science applications of simulation methods provides possible answers to this question (see also Manzo, 2004a).

36Though in sociology both the idea of simulating the mechanisms underlying social phenomena and the first real simulation attempts date from the 1960s and 70s, [26] it was not until the late 1980s that simulation methods became a focus of the real methodological and technical debate that extended to a considerable segment of the social sciences (Bruderer and Maiers, 1997; Hummon, 1990, p. 65; Troitzsch, 1997, p. 45; Whicker and Sigelman, 1991). [27] Without going so far as to speak of a “simulation era” (Hartmann, 1996, p. 77, p. 79, p. 84, p. 98) or a “new way of doing social science” (Gilbert, 1999a, 1486), we can only observe that simulation methods are currently emerging from their earlier marginality. Their place in sociological analysis seems destined to become stronger (Hanneman, 1995; Hummon, 1990; Halpin, 1999; Moretti, 2000,2002). A “computational sociology” project is beginning to take shape (Heise, 1995; Hummon and Fararo, 1995; Macy and Willer, 2002). [28]

37A general definition and concise description of a specific technique will surely give a clearer idea of the nature of this approach.

38Above and beyond the specificities of the various techniques, we can begin to define “simulation” by stating that it is the execution of a program that translates a theoretical system (representing an object of analysis) into a set of algorithms written in a specialized computer language. By this means, the behavior of this system may be studied and observed as it evolves dynamically under different conditions (see for example Macy, 2001, p. 14439; Moretti, 2000, p. 137; Troitzch, 1997, p. 46; Klein, 2002-2003, p. 7; Hanneman and Patrick, 1997; Hartmann, 1996, p. 83; Heise, 1995). The complex nature of this definition is due to the fact that simulation more closely resembles a family of techniques (clearly and pedagogically presented in Gilbert and Troitzsch, 1999) that share a common methodological spirit –this is what the foregoing definition tries to convey to the reader– rather than a single method with clearly standardized operating protocols. This is why certain authors readily use the artistic metaphor when defining the nature of the activity performed by practitioners of this approach (Axelrod, 1997a; Marney and Tarbert, 2000; Whicker and Sigelman, 1991, ch. 8). To illustrate, we can consider a type of simulation known in the literature as the “multiagent system” (Davidsson, 2002), [29] which is particularly promising for sociological analysis (Macy and Willer, 2002; Sawyer, 2003,2004a, 2004b, 2005) but also for economics (Phan, 2004), political science (Axelrod, 1997b; Cederman, 2001; Johnson, 1999) and the social sciences in general (Amblard and Phan, 2006). This technique which is becoming increasingly widespread also complexifies another method, the “cellular automata” (Weisbuch 1992) [30] well-known to biologists and physicists. As the name suggests, a multiagent system is made up of a set of n elementary units (named “automata” or “agents”). The researcher can program both the behavior of these units, either singly or grouped into subsets, and the way the units (or groups of units) interact in time. The aim of the technique is to observe how the system of interaction between agents evolves and its final “emerging” configuration. Being able to study the behavior of the system by way of different actor models and/or different interdependence structures and to model the recursiveness that gets established among the different levels of analysis (actions, interactions, aggregate products of interactions, etc.) is surely what makes this method so appealing (see also Manzo, 2007a).

39But does it offer methodological advantages genuinely specific to simulation or should its recent accelerated diffusion in the social sciences be explained rather by “methodological mode” logic ? In other words, why should we simulate ?

40I see three main reasons.

41First, it can be claimed that simulation has a positive impact on sociological theory (Collins, 1992; Fararo, 1989, p. 158; Hanneman, 1995; Hanneman, Collins and Mordt, 1995; Hanneman and Patrick, 1997; Troitzsch, 1997, p. 48). As the above definition suggests, all simulations require preliminary modeling. This step brings the matter of theoretical thinking in the research process back to the fore : simulation methods give theory back its function of orienting sociological analysis. Second, simulation analysis increases the theory’s degree of formalization. The operation of translating the initial theoretical propositions into a series of algorithms that the computer can read requires the researcher to specify the structure and shape of relations among the model’s analytic components (Hanneman et al., 1995, p. 3; Jacobsen and Bronson, 1997, p. 98, p. 99; Kliemt, 1996, p. 20). Likewise, the fact that the computer has to be able to read the model requires constant control of its internal logical consistency (Collins, 1992, pp. 647-648). Lastly, simulation complexifies the theory in that it allows for observing the behavior of a theoretical system under a variety of initial conditions (Bainbridge, 1995, p. 483, p. 484; Fararo, 1989, p. 238; Hanneman et al., 1995; Hanneman, 1995; Hanneman and Patrick, 1997; Hegselmann, 1996, pp. 222-230).

42Second, simulation methods–some more than others, of course– represent a viable technical solution for making generative mechanism reasoning operative. One is struck in reading this literature by the recurrence of such terms as “mechanism”, “process”, “underlying process”, “causal processes”, “underlying generative mechanisms”. [31] And the link between simulation methods and generative mechanism modeling is often explicitly asserted (Coleman, 1965, p. 95 : Fararo, 1989, p. 139; Edling, 2002, p. 213; Gilbert, 1994,1996a, 1999a; Kliemt, 1996, p. 14, p. 16, p. 19; Schelling, 1971). [32] Specifically, the biunivocal relation between a “generative epistemology” and “multiagent systems” is being increasingly recognized and accepted (Cederman, 2005; Epstein, 2006). This appreciable property of simulation analysis derives from the very core of the technique, namely the operation of writing a program that incorporates the theoretical model to be studied–this is termed “model translation” (Whicker and Sigelman, 1991, p. 37). Writing a series of algorithms that specify how and why the variables are linked to each other amounts in fact to postulating a series of generative mechanisms. [33] “To simulate” means to engender a structure of data from a set of theoretically significant rules that one assumes to be the foundation of the phenomenon under study (Halpin, 1999, p. 1500; Hanneman, Collins, and Mordt, 1995, p. 5). Direct modeling of the mechanism in this way is made possible by the use of a formal programming language. This allows us to “drive” the mechanism by dialoguing with the computer–to observe its dynamic form in action so to speak. In this sense–and without wishing to underestimate the difficulties involved in programming (Bruderer and Maiers, 1997; Gilbert, 1996c; Heise, 1995; Troitzsch, 1996)– the computer language can help overcome certain difficulties posed by both natural and mathematical languages, since the former may imply logically unmasterable complexity while the second can present analytically unmanageable complexity (Axtell, 2000; Coleman, 1965, p. 105; Collins, 1992, pp. 643-644; Epstein, 2006; Gilbert, 1996a, p. 449, 1999a, p. 1485; Gilbert and Troitzsch, 1999, p. 6; Hanneman et al., 1995, pp. 8-9; Johnson, 1999, p. 1511, p. 1514, p. 1518, p. 1526; Troitzsch, 1997, p. 47, p. 48).

43The third methodological advantage that helps explain the appeal of simulation methods, particularly that of “agent-centered” ones, is their ability to powerfully, flexibly model the multi-level nature of social reality (Coleman, 1965, p. 91, p. 94, p. 96; Gilbert, 1996b, p. 1, pp. 6-7,1999a, p. 1487,1999b; Grémy, 1977, p. 40, p. 71; Hanneman, 1995, p. 461; Macy, 2002, p. 144, pp. 147-148, p. 161). Specifically, simulation allows for studying how complex, unexpected consequences are engendered at the macro level from relatively simple situations at the micro level (Gilbert, 1996a, p. 452; Gilbert and Troitzsch, 1999, pp. 9-12). This property of some simulation methods derives from their ability to handle the problem of interdependence; that is, the way a plurality of elementary units interact reciprocally and, quite often, non-linearly (Latané, 1996, p. 290, p. 291; Kliemt, 1996, p. 20; Nowak and Lewenstein, 1996, p. 255, pp. 256-257, p. 258, p. 259). In modeling the meso level, simulation analysis proves a good candidate for improving our understanding of the micro-macro problem. Once again it is the computer language that allows for obtaining such results. Certain sophisticated types of programming–namely the family of languages defined as “object-oriented”– facilitate the construction of complex models where the behavior of each basic unit, the interactions among such units and the reciprocal references between the “local” and the “global” can be modeled with great precision.

44In what sense, then, can it be claimed that empirical quantitative sociology could benefit from a closer tie to simulation methods ? If we recall the problems mentioned earlier, it can be claimed that these techniques reinforce that type of sociology precisely where it is weakest. Given that variable sociology tends to underestimate the role of theory, simulation works to strengthen theoretical models. Given that the language of variables underestimates the plurality of levels specific to sociological analysis and favors linear relations, simulation methods represent a powerful technical support for handling the micro-macro problem, and by directly modeling structures of interdependence among agents, they favor a “configurational”, non-linear view of causation. Given that variable analysis requires generative mechanism reasoning to explain the empirical regularities it brings to light, simulation constitutes a tool for formally studying the mechanisms of phenomena production (Gilbert and Troitzsch, 1999). [34]

45The soundness of arguments in favor of a virtuous combining of the language of variables and simulation analysis has begun to be recognized in the literature. [35]

46Michael Macy and Robert Willer (2002, p. 162) affirm that “agent-based models use simulation to search for causal mechanisms that may underlie statistical associations”. John Goldthorpe (1999, p. 158), discussing how it might be possible to test generative mechanisms constructed at the theoretical level, notes : “The simulation approach to hypothesis testing is not at a very advanced stage. Nonetheless, there are by now at least indications that its potential in helping to integrate theoretical and empirical quantitative work is becoming more fully appreciated.” Peter Hedstrom (2005, ch. 6) seems to be explicitly moving in this direction. Lastly, it is worthwhile quoting Brendan Halpin : “This interface between statistics, simulation, and sociological theory is critically important for the development of a sociology that is both theoretically sound and empirically founded, particularly when it comes to dealing with issues that are inherently complex.” (1999, p. 1501; see also p. 1503).

Recent developments in sociology of social stratification

47One research area where empirical quantitative sociology has taken an extremely complex, sophisticated form is sociology of social stratification (Cobalti, 1995; Ballarino and Cobalti, 2003; Raftery, 2001). Not by chance was it systematically chosen as an exemplary case of the limitations of variable analysis (Cherkaoui, 2005, ch. 2; Esser, 1996; Sorensen, 1998). I make the same choice here, though with the opposite purpose, my aim being to show that social stratification sociology today represents a research area where an attempt is clearly being made to revisit variable sociology with the insights discussed in the preceding sections.

48The first sign of change concerns awareness and explicit acceptance of the methodological limits of variable analysis, particularly its a-theoreticalness and explanatory insufficiencies. John Goldthorpe (2000b, p. 230) writes : “Sociologists engaging in quantitative analysis of social mobility, or indeed of other macrosociological phenomena, have, I believe, often shown an insufficient appreciation of the importance of theory; and, in particular, in failing to see that such analysis, no matter how sophisticated it may be, cannot itself substitute for theory in providing explanations of the empirical findings that it produces.” Though sociologists of stratification are not always ready to acknowledge all the effects of this “overestimation” of the power and explanatory value of the multivariate statistical tools (Goldthorpe, 2003b, p. 33n), the direction of the shift in perspective is clearly outlined. This is confirmed by another fact : since at least the mid-1990s, the literature shows a number of studies that seek to nourish stratification sociology with an explanatory theory constructed specifically in terms of rational action and generative mechanisms (Barbera, 2004, p. 99, p. 148; Breen and Jonsson, 2005; Goldthorpe, 2003b, pp. 19-25; Grusky, 2001,25). [36]

49In this connection, studies bearing on the first phase of the social position transmission process, namely “origin —> educational attainment”, are the most advanced (see Barone, 2005; Manzo, 2004b [37] ). In John Goldthorpe’s first version of an explanatory theory of educational inequalities based on the rational actor hypothesis (1996b, pp.167-178), the notion of generative mechanism is implicitly present but the term “generative processes” is used only once (ibid, p. 162). A year later, Goldthorpe and Breen published “Explaining Educational Differentials : Towards a Formal Rational Action Theory” (1997), and it is here that the theory takes it full, mathematicized form, the point being to show that the empirically observed regularities “reflect action on the part of children and their parents that can be understood as rational” (ibid, p. 184, pp. 202-203). Reasoning in terms of generative mechanisms is here explicitly adopted. [38] Jan Jonsson and Robert Erikson (2000) propose an explanatory model of educational inequalities inspired in large degree by the same methodological principles. [39] The rational actor hypothesis (ibid., p. 347, pp. 358-368) and the notion of generative mechanisms (ibid., p. 347, p. 349, p. 362, p. 373) constitute the basic components for constructing a theory to explain the genesis of the empirical regularities describing the phenomenon : “One way of using the individual-decision model presented above, and the proposed mechanisms connected to the family of origin and the structure of the school system, is for trying to understand relevant empirical regularities.” (ibid., p. 368).

50These theoretical works have in fact already elicited a number of empirical developments. Antonio Schizzerotto (1997) takes off from rational individual strategies to explain the low level of education participation at the upper secondary and tertiary education levels of the Italian school system. Ralf Becker (2003) uses a complex model of rational school choice to analyze the increase in school participation in Germany since the 1950s, consistently linking the languages of mechanisms and variables linking (ibid., p. 2, p. 3, p. 4, p. 6, p. 13). Steffen Hillmert and Marita Jacob (2003) adopt a rational choice perspective enriched with human capital theory to study the effects of the presence of a vocational training track on scholastic inequalities at the higher levels of the German school system. The methodological principle guiding their analysis is the following : “We use a rational-choice approach to explain persisting differentials in educational decisions by looking at the cause mechanisms and generative processes of the association of social origin and educational outcomes.” (ibid., p. 321). Richard Davies, Eskil Heinesen and Anders Holm (2002) have tried to empirically assess from Danish data the relevance of the essential mechanism in the Goldthorpe-Breen model compared to the hypotheses that can be derived from the human capital theory. Richard Breen and Meir Yaish (2006) have also tried to empirically test the “relative risk aversion” mechanism on English data; to date, this study is the most direct attempt at empirically estimating the crucial generative mechanism of the Goldthorpe-Breen model (see also Holm and Jaeger, 2006). That model is also at the center of Roy Nash’s study (2003) and that of Gøsta Esping-Andersen and Josep Mestres (2003). Both of these articles attempt a critique of the model with the purpose of reevaluating the empirical effect of the socialization process on the emersion of educational inequalities. [40] Gabriele Ballarino and Fabrizio Bernardi (2001) have tried to empirically test the Erikson-Jonsson model : their analysis on the basis of “time budget” micro-data starts with the observation that the “mechanisms” responsible for the aggregate results have not been sufficiently analyzed by empirical social stratification research.

51The penetration of the generative mechanism notion can also be detected in studies of the inequalities that structure access to the job market. [41] Barbara Reskin’s article (2003) is a veritable manifesto in this area. The title itself –“Including Mechanisms in our Models of Ascriptive Inequality”– expresses the author’s programmatic intentions. Reskin defines mechanisms as “the processes that convert inputs (or independent variables) into outputs (or dependent variables)” (ibid., p. 7), declaring that only by adopting analysis in terms of mechanisms – i.e., constructing “how-explanations” (ibid., p. 1)– can the discrepancy between technical sophistication and explanatory power in empirical research into inequalities in job market access be reduced. She suggests the need to systematically model four types of “mechanisms”: “intrapsychic”, “interpersonal”, “societal” and “organizational” (ibid., pp. 8-14).

52Lastly, rational action and mechanisms are acquiring a place in some analyses of the relative aspect of social mobility. John Allen Logan (1996) outlines what he defines as the “random matching model of opportunity” (ibid., p. 175, p. 180), a microsociological model of the interaction process between two groups of actors assumed to be rational : employers and jobseeking individuals. The model formally defines the rules (ibid., pp. 177-179) and processes (pp. 179-180) that allow these two social groups to meet up with each other. Maurizio Pisati (1997) places the notion of generative mechanism at the core of a comparative empirical analysis of Italian and American mobility regimes. He explicitly accepts a “generative modeling” strategy and his stated aim is to construct “a theoretical model for the explanation of mobility regimes in terms of underlying generative mechanisms” (ibid., p. 180). [42] John Goldthorpe has also worked on constructing a theory of relative mobility in terms of rational action. In his “Outline of a theory of social mobility” (2000b), he asserts the need for a micro-foundation to explain the “intrinsic” association between origin and destination (ibid., p. 237) and recognizes the notion of “mobility strategies” as a possible means of reaching this end (ibid., pp. 238-243). [43] The methodological principle driving the theory is defined as follows : “providing theoretical accounts or narratives that can show them to be capable of generating the empirical regularities in relative mobility rates that require explanation and at the same time to be rational, and thus intelligible, responses by individuals to the situations in which they find themselves” (ibid., p. 244). An article by Mohamed Cherkaoui (2005, ch. 6) completes this framework. Cherkaoui stresses the central role that the generative mechanism notion should play if the aim of mobility studies is to construct macro-social empirical generalizations. [44]

53To demonstrate the existence in quantitative social stratification sociology of a process of methodological restructuration that is being guided by the ideas discussed in the second part of this article, we need to be able to identify studies where simulation methods are coupled with variable analysis with the purpose of applying mechanism reasoning. Though there are still very few such studies, two of those cited above do use a simulation procedure : Hillmert and Jacob (2003, pp. 326-332, p. 333) and Logan (1996, pp. 186-190). These two analyses use similar logic, in that simulation analysis is used to “drive” the mathematical equations that specify the generative mechanisms of the phenomenon, given that certain parameters cannot be estimated empirically. The types of numerical simulation used are relatively simple. This type of simulation may also be identified in two other studies, though it is used only for methodological purposes and not substantive ones. Hellevik (1997) uses a sort of numerical simulation to demonstrate that the odds-ratio does not necessarily produce the most accurate image of inequality trends (ibid., p. 376, p. 378, pp. 383-389) and that their “insensitivity to the margins” is operative under more specific conditions than sociological social stratification literature might lead us to believe (ibid., p. 394, n. 6). [45] Jones, Wilson and Pittelkow (1990, pp. 196-199, p. 203, pp. 208-209), on the other hand, use numerical simulation to choose between different (log-linear) specifications on a single mobility table, specifications that fit the data equally well. Though these studies clearly suggest there is a space for simulation methods within stratification sociology, the fact is that the types of simulation permitting particularly strong and flexible use of mechanism reasoning remain largely unknown in this area of research. A notable exception is Moretti’s attempt (2004, pp. 131-149) to outline a “multiagent” model using LISP, the purpose being to formalize certain generative mechanisms of the Italian intragenerational mobility regime. The work begun by Chattoe and Heath (2001) likewise deserves to be closely followed. There are also studies that, though remaining outside “classic” mobility sociology, show the possibility of effectively applying “object-oriented” programming languages to social stratification problems (Duong and Reilly, 1995; Fararo and Butts, 1999, pp. 48-64). [46]

54Attentive examination of stratification sociology literature thus shows that there are signs of change in the way empirical quantitative sociology in this area is practiced. The limitations of variable analysis are being recognized; there is increasing acceptance of rational action theory and generative mechanism~centered explanatory modes as essential complements to descriptive statistical analysis; simulation methods are beginning, timidly, to claim a certain legitimacy. As I see it, these “tensions” are fully inscribed in the analytic framework of “empirical quantitative sociology revisited” discernible in the recent methodological debates reconstructed here.

55This analysis of certain currents of contemporary sociological literature purports to show that a growing number of authors are converging more or less directly toward a research program that may be summed up thus : describe by means of variables —> explain by means of mechanisms —> formalize by means of simulations. Reference is to a complex image of quantitative research involving strict integration of cognitive operations (description, explanation, modeling), languages (verbal, mathematical, computational) and technical tools (statistics and simulation) that may at first sight seem hard to combine. [47] Among the sociologists considered here, Goldthorpe proposes a particularly synthetic, explicit version of this “alliance”. He advises limiting use of multivariate statistical analysis to description (1999, p. 152, p. 153, 2000c, p. 258) and combining such analysis with a theory of action (1996a; 2000c, p. 258) and with reasoning in terms of mechanisms (1999, pp. 151-154). Lastly, he acknowledges that simulation can provide a useful basis for such reasoning (1999, p. 158).

56But it can be shown that this undeniable movement within a significant part of contemporary sociology makes use of ideas that have in fact already been present in the sociological community for quite some time. We may conclude with a brief exercise in sociology of knowledge, asking why such a research program has only recently come to be recognized as relevant and legitimate.

57First, it is worthwhile recalling briefly some of the main protagonists in this longer and thus more distant history. There are of course the classical sociologists, particularly–and obviously– Max Weber. [48] Several times in the theoretical and methodological essays (Weber, 1903-1906, pp. 69-70, p. 81, 1913, p. 316,1917) as well as in the first chapter of Economy and Society (1922, p. 39), Weber explicitly claims that “rule and number knowledge” should be systematically combined with “knowledge reached through interpretation” since an empirical regularity only has meaning if it can be related to the subjective activity of the actors; conversely, an interpretation can only constitute a causally accurate statement if there are accompanying proofs of the empirical regularity engendered by such activity. As Weber explains in the first paragraph of The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism, the empirical association between worldly occupations and the Protestant denomination has already been fully brought to light; the problem “is to explain it” (1904, p. 83n). [49] The idea of linking the work of demonstrating empirical regularities with that of analyzing generative mechanisms was then explicitly put forward by certain epistemologists in the early 1970s. The works of Rom Harré (1972, p. 18, p. 137, p. 179, p. 183; Harré and Secord, 1972, p. 66, p. 70, p. 125) and Mario Bunge (1973,1983) are particularly important in this connection. And it was also during the 1970s that these ideas began to appear quite explicitly among sociologists. Raymond Boudon, for example, proposed systematically combining statistical analysis, explanation in terms of mechanisms, and simulation methods. Methodological texts (Boudon, 1965,1967, 1977a, 1979a, pp. 51-52, p. 62, p. 63n, 1979b, ch. 7), empirical applications (Boudon, 1973; Davidovitch and Boudon, 1964), as well as exchanges with researchers using different methodological approaches from his own (Boudon, 1976) attest to this author’s effort to develop and defend these ideas. [50] Other highly innovative empirical research studies dating from the same period were done by Harrison White (1970) and Aage Sorensen (1977, 1979); in these studies the methodological objective of modeling the processes and generative mechanisms underlying the macro phenomena under study was explicitly pursued and fully attained. [51]

58It is therefore undeniable that the intellectual and cognitive resources for reformulating empirical quantitative sociology have long been available to sociologists. And yet these ideas only very recently began to be discussed explicitly and systematically. Why ? What explains such slow reception and diffusion ?

59The first explanatory factor may have to do with the influence of positivist epistemology during the process of institutionalizing the sociology discipline, above all in developing protocols for quantitative empirical analysis (Barbera, 2004, p. 14; Bunge, 1997; Cherkaoui, 2005, ch. 4). From this perspective the resistance to accepting an explanatory methodology–generative mechanisms– centered on an analytical unit–the mechanism– that by definition cannot be directly observed, measured or “made operative” is understandable. Moreover, the epistemological nature of mechanisms is not comparable to that of “laws”: the scope of a mechanism is smaller, less general, than that of a nomological proposition (Elster, 1998, p. 49, pp. 51-52, p. 62,2003, ch. 1). The fact is, as Cuin remarks (2003), the current intellectual contingency tends to discredit naive positive attitudes as well as nomothetic impulses. As I see it, this may have helped make the idea of generative mechanisms more acceptable to empirical quantitative sociologists.

60The second point is that despite the fact that the “generative mechanism” notion and the idea of coupling it with the “variable” concept are not new, the way they were presented may have diminished their visibility and thereby slowed reception. Reading the “precursors”, one realizes that one of the following three situations holds : 1) these ideas were often discussed in an analytic and argumentative framework where they were not the author’s main focus; 2) they were applied in concrete research studies that did not discuss them explicitly or in any detail; 3) they were presented in narrowly diffused texts. [52]

61Third, the problems specifically linked to simulation methods have very likely made those methods hard to accept as a source for enriching empirical quantitative analysis. Among those problems should be mentioned an intrinsic difficulty of the approach : writing the program that translates the theoretical model into a set of instructions the computer can read (Bruderer and Maiers, 1997, p. 90; Whicker and Sigelman, 1991, ch. 5). This problem has not been entirely resolved today (Gilbert, 1994,1996c; Gulyas, 2003; Johnson, 2003), and it is easy to imagine the resistances it provoked in decades when interdisciplinarity was less widespread than it is today. It is worthwhile recalling an oft-raised objection to simulation methods, namely their irrealism, deriving from the simplifications required if a simulation is to run correctly (Johnson, 1999, p. 1524; Macy, 2001, pp. 14441-14443; Nowak and Lewenstein, 1996, p. 250). It is likely that due to the effect of theories of complexity and chaos, we are more willing today to accept the idea that extremely complex configurations can emerge from relatively simple initial conditions (Hegselmann et al., 1996; Nowak and Lewinstein, 1996, pp. 256-257). Third, simulation techniques (some more than others) encounter resistance from quantitative sociologists because of their weakness in the application stage (difficulty of empirically initializing many parameters, for example) and model assessment. Simulation practitioners do not deny the reality of these problems (Collins, 1992, p. 649; Hedstrom, 2005, ch. 6; Boero and Squazzoni, 2005; Whicker and Sigelman, 1991, p. 67). A less naive, technicist vision of statistical testing–see above § 1– as well as recent progress in comparing simulated and empirical data (Moss and Edmonds, 2005; Fararo and Butts, 1999; Logan, 1996; Snijders, 1997,2001) –may nonetheless have nuanced the perception of this objective difficulty. The last factor that has probably worked to inhibit acceptance of simulation methods in sociology has to do with their being epistemologically and technically hybrid. As Hanneman, Collins and Mordt pointed out (1995, pp. 5-6), the simulation approach can be ranked with neither quantitative or qualitative methods. Its components are methodologically heterogeneous : logical and/or mathematical formalization, attention to types of logic used by actors, modeling of interdependence structures, sensitivity to context variability, etc. This may be displeasing to purists [53] on the quantitativist and qualitativist side alike, the first seeing it as insufficient rigor and formalization, the second viewing it as the latest attempt at modeling what cannot be modeled.

62Though partial, this configuration of elements may help us understand why the sociological community began only belatedly to take into account methodological propositions for reformulating empirical quantitative sociology that have in fact been available since the 1960s and 70s. Now that this move has been made, it is important to confirm the usefulness of this program for quantitative sociological analysis by means of empirical research practice. I have begun working on this task (see Manzo, 2006a, 2006b, 2007b) but the road ahead is a long one.

63Translation : Amy Jacobs
Previously published : RFS, 2005,46, 1

Notes

  • (1)
    This approach is designated in the literature by means of several labels : “variablecentred methodology” (Abell, 1984), “variableoriented approach” (Ragin, 1987, ch. 4), “variable-based approach” (Abbott, 1992a, p. 441), “standard positivist analysis” (Abbott, 1992b, p. 62), “variable sociology” (Esser, 1996), “quantitative analysis of large-scale data sets” (Goldthorpe, 1996a), “sociologia quantitativa” (Corbetta, 1999), “positivist sociology” (Cherkaoui, 2005, ch. 4). I prefer to speak of quantitative empirical sociology since “variable sociology” does not exhaust quantitative sociology; there is also purely theoretical quantitative sociology; i.e., mathematical sociology, with its own status and legitimacy (Collins, 1992, pp. 619-640; Fararo, 1984, p. 219,1997, p. 91; Edling, 2002, p. 202). There is not enough space here to take up the question of the soundness of the term “quantitative sociology”, though it is an important question. Also, the epistemological debate on the ambiguities of the distinction between quantitative and qualitative approaches surely deserves more attention than I can give it here (see, for example, Agodi, 1996; Cannavo, 1988; Cardano, 1991).
  • (2)
    The potential of these proposals is currently being de bated. On Abbott’s, s ee Halpin and Chan ( 1998); Levine (2000); Santoro (2003); Wu (2000). The Journal of Mathematical Sociology devoted a special issue to A bell’s wor k (Jour nal of Mathematical Sociology, 1993, 18, nos. 2-3). What seems certain at least f or the time being is that improvement attempts have been quite limited, in that they have not been able to surmount the descriptivism specific to variable sociology. Furthermore, the very notion of “narrative” raises more problems than it solves, as Hempel had already pointed out (1965, pp. 447-453).
  • (3)
    Recognizing this does not mean denying the importance of “criticism from the outside ”. Such attac ks have in fact helpe d s ensitize “quantitative sociologists” to the limitations of their analyses and thus to fuel debate “within” the quantitative approach.
  • (4)
    “It is in turn generally agreed that, far from theory being output from causal path and suchlike analysis, it is, rather, necessary input to them”, writes Goldthorpe (1996a, p. 98). “U nfortunately, sociologis ts over the las t decades have become less, rather than more, competent at translating theoretical ideas into m odels to be estima ted by statistical techniques”, writes Sorensen (1998, p. 239).
  • (5)
    In this connection, Cherkaoui (2005, ch. 4) and Wunsch (1994, p. 30) observe that, without theoretical reasoning, both the “strong closure hypothesis” and the “weak closure” one (the first more than the second) are extremely hard to justify.
  • (6)
    Writes Sorensen : “The introduction of independent var iables as controls in a multivariate statistical model is not usually seen as specif ying a theory. [...] The result is a c onceptually meaningles s list of variables preventing any kind of substantive conclusion” (1998, pp. 243-244).
  • (7)
    “Typically, the assumptions in a statistical model are quite hard to prove or disprove, and little ef fort is spent in that dir ection”, writes David Freedman (1991a, p. 311).
  • (8)
    See V allet (2004) for a caref ul discussion of this remarkable work.
  • (9)
    The authors’ main thesis : “We cannot know w hether the causal ef fect is large or small, positive or negative, present or absent without additional knowledge that cannot be obtained from the data.” (Clogg and Haritou, 1997, pp. 105-106). Similar claims are made on pp. 94,96,100,103,104.
  • (10)
    Andrew Abbott puts this criticism as follows : in the framework of empirical quantitative sociology, “variables do things, not social actors” (1992a, p. 293; also 1992b, pp. 54-62). This problem is widely recognized in the literature; see among others Abell (1984, p. 309, p. 310, pp. 317-318); Becker (1992, p. 206); Blossfeld (1996, p. 186); Goldthorpe (1999, p. 141).
  • (11)
    “Attr ibutes deter mine each other principally as independent scales rather than as constellations of attributes; main effects are more important than interactions (main effects assumption).” (Abbott, 1992a, p. 433).
  • (12)
    My distinction between “simple aggregation pr ocess” and “com plex aggr egation m echanism s” corr esponds to Cherkaoui’s betwee n “re sultant ef fects” and “em erging effects” (1998, ch. 1). Cherkaoui locates both the basis for this conceptual distinction and the definition of macro-social level as emerging effect in Durkheim (see also Cuin, 1997). Max Weber (1922, p. 40) and more recently James Coleman (1986a, p. 1321,1990, p. 5, p. 12) proposed the same definition of the macrosocial level.
  • (13)
    Diffus ion of longitudinal data and methods for analyzing them may be of greater us e to empir ica l quantitative s ociology in resolving this second problem than the first ( i.e., taking interdependence str uctures into account). This is one of the major implications of Tom Snijder’s work on statistical processing of longitudinal data on social networks (1996, 1997,2001). Snijder shows that in order for these data, which are essential for the study of interdependence structures, to be analyzable and interpretable, available statistical techniques nee d to be combined w ith “actor-or iented” s im ulation methods. In f act, H ans- Pe ter Blossfeld’s proposal (1996, pp. 191-197,1998), recalled in the introduction, deals with only one aspect of the micro-macro problem.
  • (14)
    The Am erican economist Gary Becker’s aim to make this specific conception of the actor and action the unifying paradigm for the social sciences (1976,1993,1996,2002) surely helps explain this focus. The fact that J ames Coleman ( 1990) then directly – and s ucc essf ully– took up the challe nge in s ociology r eprese nted a f urthe r, probably decisive pull in that direction (Bouvier, 2000; D emeulenae re, 1994; Revue Fr ançais e de Sociologie, 2003, 44, 2). This led to numerous discus sions of rational choice theory; see among others Abell (1992,1996,2001); Archer and Tritter (2001); Bohman (1992); Coleman and Farar o ( 1992); Els ter ( 1986); H ardin (2001); Scheff (1992); Sociologie et Société (2002, 24, 1).
  • (15)
    This heter ogeneity has been thoroughly documented; see Blossfeld (1996); Goldthorpe (1998); Opp (2002); Udehn (2001, 2002).
  • (16)
    And two others mentioned. First, the hypothesis of rational action has a “logical privilege or priority” given that it is a required point of departure for analysis because it is a stable criterion for comparison (Goldthorpe, 1998, p. 134). James Coleman and Thomas Fararo (1992, pp. xiv-xv) speak of a “principle of order” to indicate that its absence would imply a situation of logical and empirical chaos that would block the analysis. But the idea is hardly a new one. Max Weber argued along the same lines when he affirmed that verstehende sociology was rationalist above all for reasons of heuristic utility (1903-1906, p. 69,1913, p. 306, p. 309,1917, pp. 426-427,1922, p. 32). Second, the point is to favor what may be qualified as “normative priority” in that actors themselves mean to be rational and claim this character for their actions (Elster, 1986, p. 26, 2001, p. 12763).
  • (17)
    I have borrowed from Mario Bunge (1997, p. 454,1998, p. 77) the expres sion “Boudon-Coleman diagrams”. On the micromacro problem in Boudon’s work, see also Hamlin (2000, pp. 113-114,2002).
  • (18)
    The e xpr ession “micro-m acro” frequently used here is only a linguistic formula designed to lighten the prose. It should not lead the reader to think that I favor a simplistic or dualist vision of the analytical levels sociologists can use. The constant attention given to inter de pe ndence str uctur es thr oughout this article should suffice to eliminate any such ambiguity : these structures are what found the reality and analytic relevance of the mesos ocial level. See Hannan ( 1992) f or a penetrating discussion in favor of a multi-level analytical framework for analyzing complex social systems.
  • (19)
    The title of the article–The Quantitative Analysis of Large-Scale Data Sets and Rational A ction Theor y : f or a Sociological Alliance”– published in the European Socio-logical Review, is par ticularly signif icant. G oldthor pe openly qualif ied this text as “programmatic” (2000a, p. 11, p. 19).
  • (20)
    The title of the work, Rational Choice Theory and Large-Scale Data Analysis, once again expresses the connection between literature on social action and the critical debate on variable sociology. Moreover, “rational choice theory” as used by Blossfeld and Prein has quite broad meaning (1998, p. 3).
  • (21)
    Much literature on this subject has bee n wr itte n since the ear ly 1990s : se e Blossfeld (1996); Boudon (1998); Bunge (1998, 2004); Cherkaoui (2005, ch. 4); Elster (1989, 1998,2003); Erikson (1998); Fararo (1989); H echter (1998); H edstrom (2003); Paws on (1989); Rios (2004); Schelling (1998); Sorensen ( 1998); Stinchcome ( 1991); V an den Ber g (1998). The idea of generative mechanism has been the acknowledged core of such disciplines as physics, biology and physiology since they became modern sciences (Machamer, Darden and Craver, 2000). The notion has not been so r eadily a ccepted in the s ocia l s cienc es, however, specifically sociology. Among the classic author s, implicit us e of the idea of m echanis ms seems pr esent in Tocqueville (Boudon, 2005b; Cherkaoui, 2005, ch. 1; Edling and Hedstrom, 2005; Elster, 2003, pp. 44-48), Durkheim (Cherkaoui, 1998, ch. 3,2005, ch. 2; Collins, 1992, ch. 6 and 11; Farar o, 1989, pp. 134-137, p. 345, p. 346), Simmel (Bunge, 1997, p. 412), as well as Weber (Cherkaoui, 2005, ch. 3; Hedstrom and Swedberg, 1998b, p. 5). Though Merton (1949,1967) helped introduce cer tain analytic al as pects of the notion into modern sociology, the 1960s and 1970s were the real “cradle” of the concept both epistemologically (Harré, 1972; Harré and Secord, 1972; Bunge, 1973,1983,1997) and in term s of actual use (Boudon, 1973,1976, 1979a; Davidovitch and Boudon, 1964; Fararo, 1969, Schelling, 1971). See the conclusion for further discussion of this aspect.
  • (22)
    Given that mechanisms are constructed in methodological individualism ter ms, the debates on action theory and generative mechanisms may be said to intersect and refer to each other. The reason for this was mentioned in the preceding section : because actor s alone are capable of “connecting” and “transforming” (Abell, 2004, p. 293), the only units of analysis that can claim to have causal power and significance are situated at the level of individuals and their actions.
  • (23)
    Outside sociology, the notion of “generative causality” has been put forward by a num ber of e minent thinkers. D avid Cox (1992, p. 297) suggests limiting the notion of causality “to situations where some explanation in terms of a not totally hypothetical underlying process or mechanism is available” (see also Cox and Wermuth, 1993, p. 207); A. H. Simon and Y. Iwasaki (1988, p. 150) explicitly affirm that “causality arises when a mechanism links phenomena”.
  • (24)
    This re evaluation of the s tatus of variable analysis is “radical” in Goldthorpe’s thinking. His judgment concerns both causal analysis techniques and the most recent and sophisticated statistical methods. Of the first he affirms : “Instead of being regarded as a means of inferring causation directly from data, its primary use should rather be seen as descriptive, involving the analysis of joint and conditional distribution in order to determine no more than patterns of association (or correlation).” (1999, p. 152); of the latter : “It is important that the use of rather advanced statistical techniques for these purposes of what might be called sophistic ated descr iption s hould be cle arly dis tinguished from their use in attempts at deriving causal relations directly from data analysis.” (ibid., p. 153). Hedstrom and Swedberg, no less explicit, state that we have to give up our “faith in statistical analysis as a tool for generating theor ies”, as well as the “belief in an isomorphism between statistical and theoretical models”. However, statistical analysis remains e ssential “f or descr iptive purposes and for testing sociological theories” (1998b, p. 17).
  • (25)
    Once again, Goldthorpe (2000a, p. 11, p. 19) himself qualifies this article as “programmatic”.
  • (26)
    See Archives Eur opé ennes de Sociologie (1965, 6, 1); Abelson and Caroll (1965); Boudon (1965,1967,1973,1977a, 1979a); Coleman (1962,1965); Davidovitch and Boudon (1964); Grémy ( 1971a, 1971b, 1977); Guetskow (1962); Hagerstrand (1965); Hanon (1965); Preteceille (1974); Schelling (1971); The Amer ican Behavioral Sc ientis t (1965, 8, 9).
  • (27)
    Many elements attest to this change of gears, among them the long spate of special iss ue s on the question : Social Science Computer Review (1988, 6, 1); Journal of Mathematical Sociology (1990, 15, 2); Sociological Perspectives (1995, 38, 4); American Behavioral Scientist (1999, 42, 10); American Journal of Sociology (2005, 10, 4). The on-line review created in 1998 by Nigel Gilbert at the s ociology department of the Univers ity of Surrey –“The Journal of Artificial Societies and Social Simulation: an interdisciplinary journal for the exploration and understanding of social processes by means of computer simulation” (JASSS)– is a catalyst for theoretical, methodological, and technical debate on the subject today. Collective works, most often derived f rom conferences, colloquia, and working groups or forums, multiplied in the space of a f ew yea rs (Conte, Hegse lmann a nd Ter na, 1997a; Gilbert and Conte, 1995; Gilbert and D oran, 1994; Hegs elma nn, Mueller a nd Troitzsch, 1996; Sichman, Conte and Gilbert, 1998; Troitzsch, Mueller, Gilbert and Doran, 1996). In 2002 the foundations were laid for c ons tr ucting a “Eur opean social simulation association” (Moss et al., 2002); its current internet site shows the fully developed scientific activity around the association today. Textbooks on simulation methods are finally beginning to be published; Simulation for the Social Scientist (Gilbert and Troitzsch, 1999) is one of the clear est and most instructive of these.
  • (28)
    In their def inition of the pr oject, Hummon and Fararo (1995, p. 79) specify that it “uses the ideas and technologies of modern computer science to help advance theoretical sociology through the construction and study of simulation models”.
  • (29)
    For methodological discussions and/or empirical applications of this technique, see, for example, Ba inbridge ( 1995); Cas telfr anchi (1998); Conte et al. (1997b, p. 10); Conte et al. (1998); Doran (1998); Duong and Reilly (1995); Gilbert (1996b, pp. 4-5); Gilbert and Troitzsch (1999, ch. 8 and 9); Halpin (1999, pp. 1495-1496); Johnson (1999, pp. 1522-1524, p. 1525); Macy (2001); Minar et al. (1996); Moretti ( 2000,2004); Moss ( 1998); Phan (2004); Sichman, Conte, and Gilbert (1998); Terna (1998).
  • (30)
    Hegselmann (1996) gives an excellent presentation of this method; see also Gilbert and Troitzsch ( 1999, ch. 8); Halpin (1999, pp. 1493-1494); Latané (1996, pp. 301-304); Macy (2001); Nowak and Lewinstein (1996, pp. 260-280).
  • (31)
    See for example Abelson and Carroll (1965, p. 24, p. 27, p. 30); Bainbridge (1995, p. 491); Grémy (1977, p. 60, p. 77, p. 82); Hanneman (1995, p. 458); Hanneman, Collins, and Mordt (1995, p. 3, p. 4, p. 28, p. 40); Hagerstrand (1965, p. 43, p. 46); Hartmann (1996, p. 77, p. 83, p. 91, p. 98); Nowak and Lewenstein (1996, p. 255, p. 277, p. 278, p. 279).
  • (32)
    Nigel Gilbert sees simulation as the mechanism method : “It aims to explicate the mechanisms of social processes and so perhaps could be called ‘process-centr ed analysis’.” (1996a, p. 449); “One of the benefits of computational models is that they allow the social sc ientis t to e xpr ess ideas about proces s or mecha nism in a flexible yet precise w ay.” (1999a, p. 1485).
  • (33)
    See in this connection the functional definition of mechanism given above.
  • (34)
    “Sim ulation models ar e concer ned w ith pr ocess es [...] We would expect a simulation model to include explicit representations of the processes which are thought to be at work in the social world. In contrast, a statistical model will reproduce the pattern of correlations among measured variables, but rarely w ill it be modeling the mechanisms which under lie thes e relationships.” (G ilbert and Troitzsch, 1999, p. 17).
  • (35)
    Statistical ana lysis and simulation methods have been br ought together mor e frequently than I can discuss in detail here; see, among others, Boudon (1977, p. 18); Coleman (1965, p. 100); Collins (1992); Gilbert (1994, 1996a, pp. 448-449); Gilber t and Troitzsch (1999, pp. 14-17); Halpin (1999, pp. 1499-1501); H anneman (1995, pp. 459-460); Whicker and Sigelman (1991, p. 69).
  • (36)
    This view was already being clearly outlined in the early 1970s by Raymond Boudon (1973); see the conclusion of this article.
  • (37)
    I n this study I provide a detailed recons tr uc tion of the “ra tiona l educational choice approach”, comparing it to the “cultural capital” theory that developed out of Pierre Bourdieu and Jean-Claude Passeron’s analyses. I also develop a broader-scope analysis than the one presented here of empirical literature on inequality of educational opportunity (see also Manzo and Corposanto, 2003).
  • (38)
    The section presenting the core of the model is entitle d “The generation of clas s dif fer entials” (ibid., p. 188); the analytic structure of the model is constructed in terms of mechanisms –“We then propose three mechanisms thr ough which c las s diff erentials in educational attainment may arise at the level of ‘secondary effects’.” (ibid., p. 189, p. 192), the main point of the theory being to “grasp” the “key generative processes” (ibid. p. 203).
  • (39)
    Their article, entitled “Understanding Educational Inequality : the Swedish experience”, also further develops earlier work, e.g., Erikson and Jonsson (1996), particularly the introduction and ch. 1.
  • (40)
    Both articles use recent OECD PISA s urvey data (Pr ogr amme for Inte rnational Student Assessment; see OECD, 2001). Both Nash and Esping-Andersen stress the importance of the socialization process, particularly during the early period of children’s scholastic careers. Nash’s criticism of the Goldthorpe-Breen model is har sher tha n Esping-Andersen’s.
  • (41)
    As early as the 1970s, some studies –rare but exemplary– sought to introduce or recommend modeling mechanisms and social processes in this area; see in par ticular the pioneering research of Harrison White (1970) a nd Aage Sorensen’s developments of that research (1977,1979). See further discussion in the conclusion.
  • (42)
    Pisati proposes four generative mechanisms which, by influencing the micro level of individual mobility propensity, structure the ass ociation be twe en origin a nd de stination observed at the aggregate level. The mechanisms are 1) availability of class resources for moving within social space; 2) availability of specific resources for privileged “buying” of certain social positions; 3) desirability differential for “arrival” social positions; 4) class preferences for one or another “arrival” position (ibid., pp. 181-182).
  • (43)
    The theory outlined by Goldthorpe is strictly linked to his model of educationa l inequalities (mentioned above), particularly to the mechanism of “relative r isk a version” (ibid., p. 242).
  • (44)
    Cherkaoui’s argument is based on a precise definition of the macro level; in his understanding, it is only legitimate to speak of “macro” if the interdependence structure of the individual actions potentially operative in the process of emergence of the phenomenon under study has been modeled (s ee n. 12 above). Since currently available empirical research studies in social mobility aggregate individual data simply (see comment at the end of part 1 of this ar ticle ), Cher kaoui concludes that they ar e not yet in a position to cons tr uc t macrosociological propositions. In this sense, the n, he r ecommends further developed modeling of micro-macro mechanisms, to use the ter ms of Heds tr om and Swedberg’s typology discussed above.
  • (45)
    Thesis also put forward by John Allen Logan in the article cited above (Logan, 1996, p. 175, p. 176, p. 194, p. 197, p. 198).
  • (46)
    Nathalie Bulle’s sociology of education research (1996,1999), in which certain aspects of the French and American school systems are studied by means of numerical simulation, does not entirely fit into the framework of social stratification analysis but it should nonetheless be included among these contributions.
  • (47)
    In the framework of an attempt to renew mathematical sociology, Thomas Fararo (1997, p. 94) acknowledges the difficulty of such a project, with its requirement that the researcher master a set of varied skills that can only be acquired gradually. Norman Hummon and Fararo (1995, pp. 79-80) nonetheless assert that it is this combination alone that can ensure a genuinely integrative synergy between theory and empirical data.
  • (48)
    Blossfeld (1996, p. 192) recognizes this point, though only partially; Cuin (2004) reconstructs in detail Weber’s demonstration of the need to combine “nomological knowledge” and “action theory”. See also Cherkaoui (1998, ch. 3) for an analysis of Durkheim’s contribution to the development of a n em pirical sociology dr iven by the same concer n to combine empirical data and analysis in terms of mechanisms.
  • (49)
    It is clear today that the The Protestant Ethic is in fact entirely devoted to clarifying the mechanisms that gener ate this a ssociation (Cherkaoui, 2005, ch. 3).
  • (50)
    An effort that seems to have been rewarded, as the pioneering nature of these contributions from the French sociologist and the accur acy of his s tatements ar e largely recognized at the international level; on this subject see among others Cobalti (1992); Cuin ( 1993, ch. 3); Goldthorpe (1996a, p. 96n, 1996b, p. 169,2000c, p. 259n, 2003b, p. 33); Pisati (1997); Raftery and Hout (1993, p. 59).
  • (51)
    The merits of these contributions and their im por t for contemporar y em pirical sociology have begun to be explicitly recognized and discussed; see Backman and Edling (1999); Hedstrom (2003).
  • (52)
    The first situation is represented by the above-cited contributions of Weber, Harré, and Bunge, as w ell as certain important ideas developed by Merton (1949,1967); the second by Boudon’s L’inégalité des chances (1973) and certain fundamental articles by Schelling (1971); the third by Boudon’s 1979a article as well as an important article by Fararo (1969).
  • (53)
    This occurred in the natural sciences : w hen s im ulation methods were intr oduced, ma ny scientists found them an inelegant, unsophisticated type of modeling (Troitzsch, 1996).
Français

This article offers a critical analysis of four contemporary sociological debates. Systematic analysis of the relevant literature suggests the existence of a project for reformulating the methodological foundations of empirical quantitative sociology. This reconstruction shows the emergence of the following idea: an alliance of variable analysis, mechanism methodology, and simulation techniques would be of great help in resolving some of the impasses that “standard” empirical quantitative sociology encounters. This thesis is then tested for quantitative sociology of social stratification: where there are “irrefutable signs” that the idea is becoming acceptable. Lastly, a link is established between these recent debates and older, similar proposals for resolving the problem, and the question of why the soundness of these proposals has only recently been recognized is examined.

RÉFÉRENCES

  • OnlineAbbott A., 1992a. – “From Causes to Events : Notes on Narrative Positivism”, Sociological Methods and Research, 20, 4.
  • — 1992b. – “What Do Cases Do ? Some Notes on Activity in Sociological Analysis” in C. C. Ragin, H. S. Becker (eds.), What Is a Case? Exploring the Foundations of Social Inquiry, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
  • Online— 1995. – “Sequence Analysis : New Methods for Old Ideas”, Annual Review of Sociology, 21.
  • Online— 2000. – “Reply to Levine and Wu”, Sociological Methods and Research 29, 1.
  • OnlineAbbott A., Hrycak A., 1990. – “Measuring Resemblance in Sequence Data : an Optimal Matching Analysis of Musicians’ Careers”, American Journal of Sociology, 96, 1.
  • OnlineAbbott A., Tsay A., 2000. – “Sequence Analysis and Optimal Matching Methods in Sociology”, Sociological Methods and Research, 29, 1.
  • OnlineAbell P., 1984. – “Comparative Narratives : Some Rules for Study of Action”, Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 14.
  • —1992. – “Is Rational Choice Theory a Rational Choice of Theory ?” in J. S. Coleman, T. J. Fararo (eds.), Rational Choice Theory: Advocacy and Critique, Newbury Park (Cal), Sage.
  • — 1996. – “Sociological Theory and Rational Choice Theory” in B. S. Turner (ed.), The Blackwell Companion to Social Theory, Oxford, Blackwell.
  • Online— 1998. – “Causality and Low Frequency Complex Events : the Role of Comparative Narratives”, paper given at the ISA, Montréal.
  • Online— 2001. –“Rational Choice Theory in Sociology”, International Encyclopaedia of the Social and Behavioral Sciences, Oxford, Elsevier, 19, pp.12768-12771.
  • Online— 2003. – “The Role of Rational Choice and Narrative Action Theories in Sociological Theory”, Revue Française de Sociologie, 44, 2.
  • — 2004. – “Narrative Explanation : An Alternative to Variable-Centred Explanation ?”, Annual Review of Sociology, 30.
  • Abelson R., Caroll J., 1965. – “Computer Simulation of Individual Belief Systems”, American Behavioral Scientist, 8, 9.
  • Agodi M. C., 1996 – “Qualità e quantità : un falso dilemma e tanti equivoci” in C. Cipolla, A. De Lillo (eds.), Il sociologo e le sirene. La sfida dei metodi qualitativi, Milano, FrancoAngeli.
  • Aish-Van Vaerenbergh A.-M., 1994. – “Modèles tatistiques et inférences causales : analyse des structures de covariances avec Lisrel” in R. Franck (ed.), Faut-il chercher aux causes une raison? L’explication causale dans les sciences humaines, Paris, Vrin, ch. IV.
  • OnlineAmblard F., Phan D. (eds.) 2006. – Modélisation et simulation multi-agents. Applications pour les Sciences de l’Homme et de la Société, Paris, Hermes.
  • OnlineAmerican Journal of Sociology, 2005. – “Computation”, 10, 4.
  • Archer M., Tritter J., 2001. – Rational Choice Theory: Resisting Colonisation, London, Routledge.
  • OnlineArchives Européennes de Sociologie, 1965. – Special Issue : « Simulation in Sociology », VI, 1.
  • Axelrod R., 1997a. – “Advancing the Art of Simulation in the Social Sciences” in R. Conte, R. Hegselmann, P. Terna, Simulating Social Phenomena, Berlin, Springer.
  • Online— 1997b. – The Complexity of Cooperation: Agent-Based Models of Competition and Collaboration, Princeton, Princeton University Press.
  • Axtell R., 2000. – “Why Agents ? On the Varied Motivations for Agent Computing in the Social Sciences” in Proceedings of the Workshop on Agent Simulation: Applications, Models and Tools, Argonne, Argonne National Laboratory, (Il).
  • Backman O., Edling C. R., 1999. – “Mathematics Matters : on the Absence of Mathematical Models in Quantitative Sociology”, Acta Sociologica, 42, 1.
  • Ballarino G., Bernardi F., 2001. – “Uso di dati time-budget per lo studio delle risorse familiari : capitale sociale e culturale dei genitori dei bambini in età scolare in Italia”, Quaderni di socio-logia, 2.
  • Ballarino G., Cobalti A. 2003. – Mobilità sociale, Roma, Carocci.
  • OnlineBainbridge W. S., 1995. – “Neural Network Models of Religious Beliefs”, Sociological Perspectives, 38, 4.
  • Barbera F. 2003. – “È nata una stella ? Autori, principi e obiettivi della sociologia analitica”, Rassegna Italiana di Sociologia, 4
  • Online— 2004. – Meccanismi sociali. Elementi di sociologia analitica, Bologna, Il Mulino.
  • OnlineBarone C., 2005. – “La teoria della scelta razionale e la ricerca empirica. Il caso delle disuguaglianze educative”, Rassegna Italiana di Sociologia, 3.
  • Becker G. S., 1976. – The Economic Approach to Human Behaviour, Chicago, The University of Chicago Press.
  • — 1993. – “The Economic Way of Looking at Life” in G. S. Becker, Accounting for the Tastes, Cambridge, Harvard University Press, ch. 7.
  • Online— 1996. – Accounting for the Tastes, Cambridge, Harvard University Press.
  • — 2002. – “Pousser le raisonnement économique jusqu’au bout”, Le Monde, June 7.
  • Becker H. S., 1992. – “Cases, Causes, Conjunctures, Stories and Imagery” in C. C. Ragin, H. S. Becker (eds.), What is a Case? Exploring the Foundations of Social Inquiry, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
  • OnlineBecker R., 2003. – “Educational Expansion and Persistent Inequality of Education : Utilizing Subjective Expected Utility Theory to Explain Increasing Participation Rates in Upper Secondary School in the Federal Republic of Germany”, European Sociological Review, 19, 1.
  • Berger P., 2002. – “Non verso lacrime sulla sociologia”, La Stampa, 3/12, p. 27.
  • Blalock H. M., 1991. – “Are there Really any Constructive Alternative to Causal Modeling ?”, Sociological Methodology, 21.
  • Blossfeld H.-P., 1996. – “Macro-Sociology, Rational Choice Theory, and Time : Theoretical Perspective on the Empirical Analysis of Social Processes”, European Sociological Review, 12, 2.
  • Online— 1998. – “A Dynamic Integration of Micro- and Macro-Perspective Using Longitudinal Data and Event History Models” in H.-P. Blossfeld, G. Prein, Rational Choice Theory and Large-scale Data Analysis, Boulder Co., Westview Press, ch. 14.
  • Blossfeld H.-P., Prein G., 1998. – Rational Choice Theory and Large-Scale Data Analysis, Boulder Co., Westview Press.
  • Blumer H., 1956. – “Sociological Analysis and the ‘Variable’”, American Sociological Review, 21, 6.
  • Boero R., Squazzoni F. 2005. – “Does Empirical Embeddedness Matter ? Methodological Issues on Agent-Based Models for Analytical Social Science”, Journal of Artificial Societies and Social Simulation, 8, 4.
  • Bohman J., 1992. – “The Limits of Rational Choice Explanation” in J. S. Coleman, T. J. Fararo (eds.), Rational Choice Theory: Advocacy and Critique, Newbury Park (Cal), Sage.
  • Bohrnstedt G. W., Knoke D., 1998. – Statistica per le scienze sociali, Bologna, Il Mulino. (Trans. Statistics for Social Data Analysis, Itasca, Peacock Publishers, 1994).
  • Boudon R., 1965. – “Réflexion sur la logique des modèles simulés”, Archives Européennes de Socio-logie, VI, 1.
  • — 1967. – “Simulation et analyse des processus” in R. Boudon, L’analyse mathématique des faits sociaux, Paris, Plon, ch. IX.
  • Online— 1973. – L’inégalité des chances. La mobilité sociale dans les sociétés industrielles, Paris, Armand Colin.
  • — 1976. – “Comment on Hauser’s Review of Education, Opportunity, and Social Inequality”, American Journal of Sociology, 81, 4.
  • — 1977a. – « Les modèles expérimentaux » in R. Boudon, J.-P. Grémy, Les modèles en sociologie, Lemtas, Paris.
  • — 1977b. – Effets pervers et ordre social, Paris, Presses Universitaires de France.
  • — 1979a. – “Generating Models as a Research Strategy” in R. K. Merton, J. S. Coleman, P. H. Rossi, Qualitative and quantitative social research, New York, The Free Press.
  • Online— 1979b. – La logique du social, Paris, Presses Universitaires de France.
  • — 1984. – La place du désordre. Critique des théories du changement social, Paris, Presses Universitaires de France.
  • — 1986. – “Individualisme et holisme dans les sciences sociales” in P. Birnbaum, J. Leca (eds.), Sur l’individualisme, Paris, Presses de la Fondation Nationale des Sciences Politiques, ch. 2.
  • — 1989. – “Subjective Rationality and the Explanation of Social Behavior”, Rationality and Society, 1, 2.
  • — 1993. – “Toward a Synthetic Theory of Rationality”, International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 7, 1.
  • — 1995. – Le juste et le vrai. Étude sur l’objectivité des valeurs et de la connaissance, Paris, Fayard.
  • Online— 1996. – “The Cognitivist Model : a Generalized Rational-Choice Model”, Rationality and Society, 8, 2.
  • Online— 1997. – Metodologia della sociologia e delle scienze sociali, Turion, Jaca Book.
  • — 1998. – “Social Mechanisms without Black Boxes” in P. Hedstrom, R. Swedberg (eds.), Social Mechanisms: an Analytical Approach to Social Theory, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
  • Online— 1999. – Le sens des valeurs, Paris, Pressses Universitaires de France.
  • — 2001. – “Which Rational Action Theory for Future Mainstream Sociology : Methodological Individualism or Rational Choice Theory ?”, European Sociological Review, 17, 4.
  • Online— 2002a. – “Théorie du choix rationnel ou individualisme méthodologique”, Sociologie et Société, 34, 1.
  • — 2002b. – Déclin de la morale? Déclin des valeurs? Quebec, Paris, Nota bene, Gallimard.
  • — 2002c. – “Sociology that Really Matters”, European Sociological Review, 18, 3.
  • — 2003. – Raison, bonnes raisons, Paris, Presses Universitaires de France.
  • Online— 2005a. – “Le ’vernis logique’: à manipuler avec précaution”, Revue Française de Sociologie, 46, 3.
  • Online— 2005b. – Tocqueville aujourd’hui, Paris, Odile Jacob.
  • Bouvier A., 2002. – “Les modèles économiques des acteurs sociaux et l’idée d’une science sociale générale. Un éclairage néo-paretien”, Travaux du GEMAS, 18.
  • Breen R., Jonsson J. O. 2005. – “Inequality of Opportunity in Comparative Perspective : Recent Research on Educational Attainment and Social Mobility”, Annual Review of Sociology, 31.
  • Breen R., Yaish M., 2006. – “Testing the Breen-Goldthorpe Model of Educational Decision Making” in L. Stephen, D. B. Morgan, D. Grusky, G. S. Fields (eds.) Frontiers in Social and Economic Mobility, Stanford, Stanford University Press.
  • Bruderer E., Maiers M., 1997. – “From the Margin to the Mainstream : an Agenda for Computer Simulations in the Social Sciences” in R. Conte, R. Hegselmann, P. Terna, Simulating Social Phenomena, Berlin, Springer.
  • OnlineBulle N., 1996. – “Simulation des choix de filière scolaire. Application à l’orientation des élèves dans le second cycle du secondaire depuis le début du siècle en France”, Revue Française de Socio-logie, 37, 4.
  • — 1999. – La rationalité des décisions scolaires, Paris, Presses Universitaires de France.
  • Bunge M., 1973. – Method, Model and Matter, Dordrecht, Reidel.
  • — 1983. – Treatise on Basic Philosophy, vol. 6 : Epistemology and Methodology II: Understanding the World, Dordrecht, Reidel.
  • — 1997. – “Mechanisms and Explanation”, Philosophy of Social Sciences, 27, 4.
  • — 1998. – Social Science under Debate: a Philosophical Perspective, Toronto, University of Toronto Press.
  • — 2004. – “How Does it Work ? The Search for Explanatory Mechanisms”, Philosophy of the Social Science, 34, 2.
  • Cannavò L., 1988. – “Qualità e quantità : tra metodologia sociologica e sociologia della scienza”, Sociologia e ricerca sociale, 28.
  • OnlineCardano M., 1991. – “Il sociologo e le muse. Qualità e quantità nella ricerca sociologica”», Rassegna Italiana di Sociologia, 32, 2.
  • Castelfranchi C., 1998. – “Simulating with Cognitive Agents : the Importance of Cognitive Emergence” in J. Sichman, R. Conte, N. Gilbert (eds.), Multi-Agent Systems and Agent Based Simulation, Berlin, Springer.
  • Cederman L.-E. 2001. – “Agent-Based Modelling in Political Science”, Political Methodology, 10, 1.
  • — 2005. – “Computational Models of Social Forms : Advancing Generative Process Theory”, American Journal of Sociology, 110, 4.
  • Chattoe E., Heath A. 2001. – “A New Approach to Social Mobility Models : Simulation as ‘Reverse Engineering’”, paper given at the British Sociological Association Jubilee Conference, A Sociological Odyssey, Manchester Metropolitan University, 9-12 April.
  • Cherkaoui M., 1998. – Naissance d’une science sociale. La sociologie selon Durkheim, Geneva, Droz.
  • Online— 2005. – Invisible Codes: Essays on Generative Mechanisms, Oxford, Bardwell Press.
  • OnlineClogg C. C., Haritou A., 1997. – “The Regression Method of Causal Inference and a Dilemma Confronting this Method” in V. R. McKim, P. S. Turner (eds.), Causality in Crisis, Notre Dame (In), University of Notre Dame Press.
  • OnlineCobalti A., 1992. – “Origine sociale e livello d’istruzione : un modello”, Polis, 6, 1.
  • — 1995. – Lo studio della mobilità sociale. Metodi e prospettive dell’indagine sociologica, Roma, Nis.
  • OnlineColeman J. S., 1962. – “Analysis of Social Structures and Simulation of Social Processes with Electronic Computers” in H. S. Guetzkow (ded.), Simulation in Social sciences: Readings, Englewood Cliffs (NJ), Prentice-Hall.
  • Online— 1965. – “The Use of Electronic Computers in the Study of Social Organization”, Archives Européennes de Sociologie, VI, 1.
  • — 1986a. – “Social Theory, Social Research and a Theory of Action”, American Journal of Sociology, 96, 6.
  • — 1986b. – “Introduction” in J. Coleman, Individual Interests and Collective Action, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
  • — 1990. – The Foundations of Social Theory, Cambridge, Harvard University Press.
  • Coleman J. S., Fararo T., 1992. – “Introduction” in J. S. Coleman, T. Fararo, Rational Choice Theory: Advocacy and Critique, Newbury Park (Ca), Sage.
  • Collins R., 1992. – Teorie sociologiche, Bologna, Il Mulino.
  • Conte R., Hegselmann R., Terna P., 1997a. – Simulating Social Phenomena, Berlin, Springer.
  • — 1997b. – “Social Simulation – A New Disciplinary Synthesis” in R. Conte, R. Hegselmann, P. Terna, Simulating Social Phenomena, Berlin, Springer.
  • Conte R., Gilbert N., Sichman J. S., 1998. – “MAS and Social Simulation : a Suitable Commitment” in J. Sichman, R. Conte, N. Gilbert, Multi-Agent Systems and Agent Based Simulation, Berlin, Springer.
  • OnlineCorbetta P., 1999. – “Metodologia e tecniche della ricerca sociale”, Bologna, Il Mulino.
  • OnlineCox D. R., 1992. – “Causality : Some Statistical Aspects”, Journal of the Royal Statistical Society, 155, Series A.
  • Cox D.R., Wermuth N., 1993. – “Linear Dependencies Represented by Chain Graphs”, Statistical Science, 8.
  • Cuin C.-H., 1993. – Les sociologues et la mobilité sociale, Paris, Presses Universitaires de France
  • Online— (ed.), 1997. – Durkheim d’un siècle à l’autre, Paris, Presses Universitaires de France.
  • Online— 2000. – Ce que (ne) font (pas) les sociologues. Petit essai d’épistémologie critique, Geneva, Droz.
  • — 2002. – “Le balancier sociologique français : entre individus et structures”, Revue Européenne de Sciences Sociales, 40, 124.
  • — 2004. – “Y a-t-il des lois sociologiques ? ” in M. Borlandi, L. Sciolla (eds.), Teorie e metodi delle scienze sociali, Bologna, Il Mulino.
  • — 2005. – “Le paradigme ‘cognitif’: quelques observations et une suggestion”, Revue Française de Sociologie, 46, 3.
  • Davidovitch A., Boudon R., 1964. – “Les mécanismes sociaux des abandons de poursuite judiciaires : analyse expérimentale par simulation”, L’Année Sociologique, 3rd series, pp. 111-244.
  • Davidsson P., 2002. – “Agent Based Social Simulation : a Computer Science View”, The Journal of Artificial Societies and Social Simulation, 5, 1.
  • Davies R., Heinesen E., Holm A., 2002. – “The Relative Risk Aversion Hypothesis of Educational Choice”, Journal of Population Economics, 15, 4.
  • Déchaux J.-H., 2002. – “L’action rationnelle en débat. Sur quelques contributions et réflexions récentes”, Revue Françaises de Sociologie, 43, 3.
  • Demeulenaere P., 1994. – “Commentaire sur James Coleman : Foundations of Social Theory”, L’Année Sociologique, 44.
  • OnlineDoran J., 1998. – “Simulating Collective Misbelief”, The Journal of Artificial Societies and Social Simulation, 1, 1.
  • OnlineDuong D. V., Reilly K. D., 1995. – “A System of IAC Neural Networks as the Basis for Self-Organi-zation in a Sociological Dynamical System Simulation”, Behavioral Science, 40.
  • OnlineEdling C. R., 2002. – “Mathematics in Sociology”, Annual Review of Sociology, 28.
  • Edling C. R., Hedstrom P., 2005. – “Analytical Sociology in Tocqueville’s Democracy in America, see http: // www. nuff. ox. ac. uk/ sociology/ Group/ Hedstrom. htm
  • Elster J., 1986. – “Introduction” in J. Elster, Rational Choice, Oxford, Basil Blackwell.
  • Online— 1989. – Nuts and Bolts for the Social Sciences, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
  • Online— 1998. – “A Plea for Mechanisms” in P. Hedstrom, R. Swedberg (eds.), Social Mechanisms. An Analytical Approach to Social Theory, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
  • Online— 2001. – “Rational Choice Theory : Cultural Concerns”, International Encyclopaedia of the Social and Behavioural Sciences, Elsevier, Oxford, vol. 19, pp. 12763-12768.
  • Online— 2003. – Proverbes, maximes, émotions, Paris, Presses Universitaires de France.
  • OnlineEpstein J., 2006. – Generative Social Science: Studies in Agent-Based Computational Modeling, Princeton, Princeton University Press.
  • OnlineErikson R., 1998. – “Thresholds and Mechanisms. A Comment on Hedstrom and Swedberg’s Chapter” in H.-P. Blossfeld, G. Prein, Rational Choice Theory and Large-Scale Data Analysis, Boulder Co., Westview Press, ch. 5.
  • Erikson R., Jonsson J. O., 1996. – Can Education Be Equalized? The Swedish Case in Comparative Perspective, Boulder Co., Westview Press.
  • Esping-Andersen G., Mestres J., 2003. – “Ineguaglianza delle opportunità ed eredità sociale”, Stato e Mercato, 67.
  • Esser H., 1996. – “What is Wrong with ‘Variable Sociology’?”, European Sociological Review, 12, 2.
  • Fararo T. J., 1969. – “Stochastic Processes” in E. F. Borgatta (ed.), Sociological Methodology, San Francisco, Jossey-Bass.
  • Online— 1984. – “Preface”, Journal of Mathematical Sociology, 10.
  • — 1989. – The Meaning of General Theoretical Sociology. Tradition and Formalisation, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
  • — 1997. – “Reflections on Mathematical Sociology”, Sociological Forum, 12, 1.
  • Fararo T. J., Butts C. T., 1999. – “Advance in Generative Structuralism : Structured Agency and Multilevel Dynamics”, Journal of Mathematical Sociology, 24, 1.
  • Freedman D. A., 1991a. – “Statistical Analysis and Shoe Leather”, Sociological Methodology, 21.
  • — 1991b. – “A Rejoinder to Berk, Blalock, and Mason”, Sociological Methodology, 21.
  • Friedman D., Hechter M., 1988. – “The Contribution of Rational Choice Theory to Macro Sociological Research”, Sociological Theory, 6.
  • Gambetta D., 1998. – « Concatenations of Mechanisms » in P. Hedstrom, R. Swedberg, (eds.), Social Mechanisms: an Analytical Approach to Social Theory, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
  • Gilbert N. G., 1994. – “Computer Simulation of Social Processes”, see http: /// www. soc. surrey. ac. uk. /sru/SRU6.html.
  • — 1996a. – “Simulation as a Research Strategy” in G. K. Troitzsch, U. Mueller, N. G. Gilbert, J. E. Doran, Social Science Microsimulation, Berlin, Springer.
  • — 1996b. – “Holism, Individualism and Emergent Properties. An Approach from the Perspective of Simulation” in R. Hegselmann, U. Mueller, G. K. Troitzsch, Modelling and Simulation in the Social Sciences from the Philosophy of Science Point of View, Dordrecht, Kluwer.
  • — 1996c. – “Environments and Languages to Support Social Simulation” in G. K. Troitzsch, U. Mueller, N. G. Gilbert, J. E. Doran, Social Science Microsimulation, Berlin, Springer.
  • — 1999a. – “Simulation : a New Way of Doing Social Science”, Computer Simulation in the Social Sciences, 42, 10.
  • — 1999b. – “Multi-level Simulation in Lisp-Stat”, Journal of Artificial Societies and Social Simulation, 2, 1, http : // www. soc. surrey. ac. uk/ JASSS/ 2/ 1/ 3. html.
  • OnlineGilbert N., Conte R. (eds.), 1995. – Artificial Societies: the Computer Simulation of Social Life, London, UCL Press.
  • Gilbert N., Doran J., 1994. – Simulating Societies: the Computer Simulation of Social Phenomena, London, UCL Press.
  • Gilbert N., Troitzsch K., 1999. – Simulation for the Social Scientist, Philadelphia, Open University Press.
  • Goldthorpe J. H., 1996a. – “The Quantitative Analysis of Large-Scale Data Sets and Rational Action Theory : For a Sociological Alliance” in J. H. Goldthorpe, On Sociology. Numbers, Narratives, and the Integration of Research and Theory, Oxford, Oxford University Press, ch. 5.
  • — 1996b. – “Class Analysis and the Reorientation of Class Theory : the Case of Persisting Differentials in Education Attainment” in J. H. Goldthorpe, On Sociology. Numbers, Narratives, and the Integration of Research and Theory, Oxford, Oxford University Press, ch. 8.
  • Online— 1997. – “The Integration of Sociological Research and Theory – Grounds for Optimism at the End of the Twentieth Century”, Rationality and Society, 9, 4.
  • Online— 1998. – “Rational Action Theory for Sociology” in J. H. Goldthorpe, On Sociology. Numbers, Narratives, and the Integration of Research and Theory, Oxford, Oxford University Press, ch. 6.
  • — 1999. – “Causation, Statistics, and Sociology” in J. H. Goldthorpe, On sociology. Numbers, Narratives, and the Integration of Research and Theory, Oxford, Oxford University Press, ch. 7.
  • — 2000a. – On sociology. Numbers, Narratives, and the Integration of Research and Theory, Oxford, Oxford University Press.
  • Online— 2000b. – “Outline of a Theory of Social Mobility” in J. H. Goldthorpe, On sociology. Numbers, Narratives, and the Integration of Research and Theory, Oxford, Oxford University Press, ch. 11.
  • Online— 2000c. – “Sociology and Probabilistic Revolution, 1830-1930 : Explaining an Absent Synthesis” in J. H. Goldthorpe, On sociology. Numbers, Narratives, and the Integration of Research and Theory, Oxford, Oxford University Press, ch. 12.
  • Online— 2003. – “Progress in Sociology : the Case of Social Mobility Research, Sociology Working Papers, Paper number 2003-08, Oxford, Department of Sociology.
  • Online— 2004. – “Sociology as Social Science and Cameral Sociology : Some Further Thoughts”, European Sociological Review, 20.
  • OnlineGoldthorpe J. H., Breen R., 1997. – “Explaining Educational Differentials : Towards a Formal Rational Action Theory” in J. H. Goldthorpe, On sociology. Numbers, Narratives, and the Integration of Research and Theory, Oxford, Oxford University Press, ch. 9.
  • Gremy J.-P., 1971a. – “Use of Computer Simulation Techniques in Sociology”, International Social Science Journal, 23, 2.
  • — 1971b. – “Les techniques de simulation” in R. Boudon, Les mathématiques en sociologie, Paris, Presses Universitaires de France.
  • — 1977. – “Les modèles simulables” in R. Boudon, J.-P. Grémy, Les modèles en sociologie, Paris, Lemtas.
  • Grusky D. 2001. – “The Past, Present, and Future of Social Inequality” in D. Grusky, Social Stratification: Class, Race, and Gender in Sociological Perspective, Boulder, Westview Press.
  • Grusky D. B., Di Carlo M., 2001. – “Should Sociologists Plod Along and Establish Descriptive Regularities or Seek a Grand Explanation of Them ?”, European Sociological Review, 17, 4.
  • Guetzkow H. 1962. – Simulations in Social Science, Englewood Cliffs (NJ), Prentice-Hall.
  • OnlineGulyas L., 2003. – “Commentaire sur ‘Learning SIMUL8 : The Complete Guide’ (and SIMUL8 version 6)”, The Journal of Artificial Societies and Social Simulation, 6, 3.
  • Hagerstrand T., 1965. – “A Montecarlo Approach to Diffusion”, Archives Européennes de Socio-logie, VI, 1.
  • Halpin B., 1999. – “Simulation in Sociology”, American Behavioral Scientist, 42, 10.
  • OnlineHalpin B., Chan T. W., 1998. – “Class Careers as Sequences : an Optimal Matching Analysis of Work-Life Histories”, European Sociological Review, 14, 2.
  • Hamlin C. L., 2000. – “L’ontologia sociale della teoria della rationalità cognitiva” in E. Di Nuoscio (dir.), Spiegazione scientifica e relativismo culturale, Roma, Luiss.
  • Online— 2002. – Beyond Relativism. Raymond Boudon, Cognitive Rationality, and Critical Realism, London, Routledge.
  • OnlineHannan T. M., 1992. – “Rationality and Robustness in Multilevel Systems” in J. S. Coleman, T. Fararo, Rational Choice Theory. Advocacy and Critique, Newbury Park, (Ca), Sage.
  • Hanneman R. A., 1995. – “Simulation Modelling and Theoretical Analysis in Sociology”, Sociological Perspectives, 38, 4.
  • Hanneman R. A., Collins R., Mordt G., 1995. – “Discovering Theory Dynamics by Computer Simulation : Experiments on State Legitimacy and Imperialist Capitalism”, Sociological Methodology, 25, 1.
  • OnlineHanneman R. A., Patrick S., 1997. – “On the Uses of Computer-Assisted Simulation Modelling in the Social Sciences”, Sociological Research on Line, 2, 2.
  • OnlineHanon B., 1965. – “The Use of Simulation in the Analysis of Business Systems”, The American Behavioral Scientist, 8, 9.
  • OnlineHardin R., 2001. – “Rational Choice Explanation : Philosophical Aspects”, International Encyclopedia of the Social and Behavioral Sciences, Oxford, Elsevier, vol. 19.
  • Harré R., 1972. – The Philosophies of Science. An Introductory Survey, Oxford, Oxford University Press.
  • OnlineHarré R., Secord P. F., 1972. – The Explanation of Social Behaviour, Oxford, Oxford University Press.
  • Hartmann S., 1996. – “The World as a Process. Simulation in the Natural and Social Sciences” in R. Hegselmann, U. Mueller, G. K. Troitzsch, Modelling and Simulation in the Social Sciences from the Philosophy of Science Point of View, Dordrecht, Kluwer.
  • Hechter M., 1998. – “The Future of Rational Choice Theory and its Relationships to Quantitative Macro-Sociological Research” in H.-P. Blossfeld, G. Prein, Rational Choice Theory and Large-Scale Data Analysis, Boulder Co., Westview Press, ch. 17.
  • OnlineHedstrom P., 2003. – “Generative Models and Explanatory Research : On Sociology of Aage Sorensen”, see http : // www. nuff. ox. ac. uk/ Sociology/ Group/ Hedstrom. htm
  • Online— 2005. – Dissecting the Social: On the Principles of Analytical Sociology, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
  • Hedstrom P., Swedberg R., 1996. – “Rational Choice, Empirical Research, and the Sociological Tradition”, European Sociological Review, 12, 2.
  • OnlineHedstrom P., Swedberg R. (eds), 1998a. – Social Mechanisms. An Analytical Approach to Social Theory, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
  • OnlineHedstrom P., Swedberg R., 1998b. – “Social Mechanisms : an Introductory Essay” in P. Hedstrom, R. Swedberg (eds.), Social Mechanisms. An Analytical Approach to Social Theory, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
  • Hegselmann R., 1996. – “Cellular Automates in the Social Sciences. Perspectives, Restrictions, and Artifacts” in R. Hegselmann, U. Mueller, G. K. Troitzsch (eds.), Modelling and Simulation in the Social Sciences from the Philosophy of Science Point of View, Dordrecht, Kluwer.
  • Hegselmann R., Mueller U., Troitzsch G. K. (eds.), 1996. – Modelling and Simulation in the Social Sciences from the Philosophy of Science Point of View, Dordrecht, Kluwer.
  • Heise D., 1995. – “Sociological Algorithms : Preface”, Journal of Mathematical Sociology, 20, 2-3.
  • Hellevik O., 1997. – “Class Inequality and Egalitarian Reform”, Acta Sociologica, 40.
  • Hempel C. G., 1965. – “Aspects of Scientific Explanation” in C. G. Hempel, Aspects of Scientific Explanation and Other Essays in the Philosophy of Science, New York, The Free Press.
  • OnlineHillmert S., Jacob M., 2003. – “Social Inequality in Higher Education. Is Vocational Training a Pathway Leading to or away from University ?”, European Sociological Review, 19, 3.
  • OnlineHolm A., Jaeger M. M., 2006. – “Relative Risk Aversion and Social Reproduction in Intergenerational Educational Attainment : Application of a Dynamic Discrete Choice Model”, Centre for Applied Microeconometrics, Department of Economics, University of Copenhagen.
  • OnlineHummon N. P., 1990. – “Computer Simulation in Sociology”, The Journal of Mathematical Sociology, 15, 2.
  • OnlineHummon N. P., Fararo T., 1995. – “The Emergence of Computational Sociology”, Journal of Mathematical Sociology, 20, 2-3.
  • Jacobsen C., Bronson R., 1997. – “Computer Simulated Empirical Tests of Social Theory : Lessons from 15 Years’ Experience” in R. Conte, R. Hegselmann, P. Terna (eds.), Simulating Social Phenomena, Berlin, Springer.
  • Johnson P. E., 1999. – “Simulation Modelling in Political Science”, Computer Simulation in the Social Sciences, 42, 10.
  • — 2003. – “Compte rendu sur Suleiman R., Troitzsch K., Gilbert N. (eds), Tools and Techniques for social science simulation”, The Journal of Artificial Societies and Social Simulation, 6, 1.
  • Jones F. L, Wilson S. R., Pittelkow Y., 1990. – “Modelling Mobility : the Use of Simulation to Choose between Near-Equivalent Models”, Quality and Quantity, 24.
  • Jonsson J. O., Erikson R., 2000. – “Understanding Educational Inequality : the Swedish Experience”, L’Année Sociologique, 50, 2.
  • Klein E., 2002-2003. – “Comprendre, concevoir, agir : les trois finalités de la simulation”, CLEFS CEA, 47.
  • Kliemt H., 1996. – “Simulation and Rational Practice” in R. Hegselmann, U. Mueller, G. K. Troitzsch (eds.), Modelling and Simulation in the Social Sciences from the Philosophy of Science Point of View, Dordrecht, Kluwer.
  • Lazega E., 2003. – “Rationalité, discipline sociale et structure”, Revue Française de Sociologie, 44, 2.
  • Lazega E., Favereau O., 2002. – “Introduction” in O. Favereau, E. Lazega (eds), Conventions and Structures in Economic Organization: Markets, Networks and Hierarchies, Cheltenham, Edward Elgar.
  • OnlineLatané B., 1996. – “Dynamic Social Impact. Robust Predictions from Simple Theory” in R. Hegselmann, U. Mueller, G. K. Troitzsch (eds.), Modelling and Simulation in the Social Sciences from the Philosophy of Science Point of View, Dordrecht, Kluwer.
  • Levine J. L., 2000. – “But What Have you Done for Us Lately ? Commentary on Abbott and Tsay”, Sociological Methodology, 29, 1.
  • OnlineLieberson S., 1985. – Making it Count. The Improvement of Social Research and Theory, Berkeley, University of California Press.
  • Lindenberg S., 1977. – “Individuelle Effekte, kollektive Phänomene und das Problem der Transformation“ in K. Eichner, W. Habermehl (eds.), Probleme der Erklärung sozialen Verhaltens, Meisenheim, Anton Hain, pp. 46-84.
  • Online— 1992. – “The Method of Decreasing Abstraction” in J. S. Coleman, T. Fararo, Rational Choice Theory: Advocacy and Critique, Newbury Park (Cal), Sage.
  • Online— 1998. – “The Influence of Simplification on Explananda : Phenomenon-Centered Versus Choice-Centered Theories in the Social Sciences” in H.-P. Blossfeld, G. Prein, Rational Choice Theory and Large-Scale Data Analysis, Boulder Co., Westview Press.
  • — 2000. – “The Extension of Rationality : Framing versus Cognitive Rationality” in F. Chazel, J. Baechler (eds.), L’acteur et ses raisons, Paris, Presses Universitaires de France.
  • — 2002. – “Social Rationality Versus Rational Egoism” in J. H. Turner (eds), Handbook of Socio-logical Theory, New York, Kluwer Academic Publisher.
  • Online— 2003. – “Coleman et la construction des institutions : peut-on négliger la rationalité sociale ?”, Revue Française de Sociologie, 44, 2
  • Logan J. A., 1996. – “Rules of Access and Shift in Demand : a Comparison of Log-Linear and Two-Sided Logit Models”, Social Science Research, 25.
  • OnlineMachamer P. K., Darden L., Craver C. F. 2000. – “Thinking about Mechanisms”, Philosophy of Science, 67.
  • OnlineMacy W. M., 2001. – « Social Simulation : Computational Approaches », International Encyclopedia of the Social and Behavioral Sciences, Oxford, Elsevier, vol. 21.
  • OnlineMacy W. M., Willer R., 2002. – “From Factors to Actors : Computational Sociology and Agent-Based Modeling”, Annual Review of Sociology, 28.
  • Manzo G., 2004a. – “Appunti sulla simulazione al computer. Un metodo attraente per la ricerca sociologica” in C. Corposanto (ed.), Metodologie non-intrusive nelle scienze sociali, Milano, Franco Angeli.
  • – 2004b. – “Verso una teoria delle diseguaglianze di opportunità educative”, Studi di Sociologia, 42, 1.
  • – 2006a. – “Generative Mechanisms and Multivariate Statistical Analysis. Modeling Educational Opportunity Inequality by Multi-Matrix Log-Linear Topological Model : Contributions and Limits”, Quality and Quantity, 40, 5, pp. 721-758.
  • Online– 2006b. – “Actions, interactions et structure dans l’émergence de la stratification sociale des diplômes : un modèle de choix discrets avec externalités”, Mathématiques et Sciences Humaines, 175, 3, pp. 53-99.
  • – 2007a. – “Progrès et urgence de la modélisation en sociologie. Du concept de ‘modèle générateur’ et de sa mise en œuvre”, L’Année Sociologique, 57, 1.
  • Online– 2007b. – “Le modèle du choix éducatif interdépendant. Des mécanismes théoriques aux données empiriques”, Archives Européennes de Sociologie, 48, 1 (in press).
  • Manzo G., Corposanto C., 2003. – “Disuguaglianze educative e loro trasformazioni nel tempo : problemi tecnici e metodologici di un’analisi compiuta mediante reti neurali artificiali”, Sociologia e Ricerca Sociale, 70.
  • Marini M. M., 1992. – “The Role of Models of Purposive Action in Sociology” in J. S. Coleman, T. Fararo, Rational Choice Theory. Advocacy and Critique, Newbury Park, (Cal), Sage.
  • OnlineMarney J. P., Tarbert H. F. E., 2000. – “Why Do Simulation ? Towards a Working Epistemology for Practitioners of the Dark Arts”, The Journal of Artificial Societies and Social Simulation, 3, 4.
  • Merton R. K., 1949. – Social Structure and Social Theory, London, The Free Press of Glencoe.
  • — 1967. – “On the Sociological Theories of the Middle Range” in R. K. Merton, On Theoretical Sociology. Five Essays, Old and New, London, The Free Press.
  • Minar N., et al., 1996. – “The Swarm Simulation System : a Toolkit for Building Multi-Agent Simulations”, see http : // www. santafe. edu/ projects/ swarm/ overview/ overwiew. html.
  • OnlineMoretti S., 2000. – “Teorie sociologiche e modelli computazionali. Problemi metodologici nella definizione di un sistema di simulazione nelle scienze sociali”, Sociologia e Ricerca Sociale, 63.
  • Online— 2002. – “Computer Simulation in Sociology : What Contribution ?”, Social Sciences Computer Review, 20, 1.
  • Online— 2004. – Modelli e conoscenza scientifica. Problemi di formalizzazione nella ricerca sociologica, Milano, Guerini scientifica.
  • OnlineMoss S., 1998. – “Social Simulation Models and Reality : Three Approaches” in J. Sichman, R. Conte, N. Gilbert, Multi-Agent Systems and Agent Based Simulation, Berlin, Springer.
  • OnlineMoss S. et al., 2002. – “An European Social Simulation Association”, The Journal of Artificial Societies and Social Simulation, 5, 3.
  • Moss S., Edmonds B. 2005. – “Sociology and Simulation : Statistical and Qualitative Cross-Validation”, American Journal of Sociology, 110, 4.
  • Nash R., 2003. – “Inequality/Difference in Education : Is a Real Explanation of Primary and Secondary Effects Possible ? », British Journal of Sociology, 54, 4.
  • OnlineNowak A., Lewenstein M., 1996. – “Modeling Social Change with Cellular Automata” in R. Hegselmann, U. Mueller, G. K. Troitzsch, Modelling and Simulation in the Social Sciences from the Philosophy of Science Point of View, Dordrecht, Kluwer.
  • OnlineOECD, 2001. – Knowledge and Skills for Life, Paris, OECD.
  • Opp K.-D., 2002. – “Le differenti versioni della teoria dell’azione razionale” in R. Boudon, P. Demeleunaere, E. Di Nuoscio, Filosofia dell’azione e teoria della razionalità, Roma, Luiss.
  • OnlinePasseron J.-C., 1991. – Le raisonnement sociologique. L’espace non-popperien du raisonnement naturel, Paris, Nathan.
  • Pawson R., 1989. – A Measure for Measures: a Manifesto for Empirical Sociology, London, Routledge.
  • Phan D., 2004. – “From Agent-Based Computational Economics towards Cognitive Economics” in P. Bourgine, J.-P. Nadal (eds), Cognitive Economics: an Interdisciplinary Approach, Berlin, Springer
  • Pisati M., 1997. – “Mobility Regimes and Generative Mechanisms : a Comparative Analysis of Italy and the United States”, European Sociological Review, 13, 2.
  • OnlinePreteceille E., 1974. – Jeux, modèles et simulations: critique des jeux urbains, Paris, Mouton.
  • Raftery A. E., 2001. – “Statistics in Sociology, 1950-2000 : a Selective Review”, Sociological Methodology, 31.
  • Raftery A. E., Hout M., 1993. – “Maximally Maintained Inequality : Expansion, Reform and Opportunity in Irish Education, 1921-1975”, Sociology of Education, 66, 41-62.
  • Ragin C. C., 1987. – The Comparative Method. Moving beyond Qualitative and Quantitative Strategies, Berkeley, University of California Press.
  • OnlineRagin C. C., Becker H. S., 1992. – What Is a Case? Exploring the Foundations of Social Inquiry, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
  • OnlineRaynaud D., 2004. – “Le raisonnement expérimental en physique et en sociologie”, Paper given at the “Centre d’étude sociologique de la Sorbonne”, 10-03-2004.
  • — 2006. – La sociologie et sa vocation scientifique, Paris, Hermann.
  • OnlineRaub W., 1982. – “The Structural-Individualist Approach : Towards an Explanatory Sociology” in W. Raub (ed.), Theoretical Models and Empirical Analyses, Utrecht, E. S. Publications.
  • Reskin B., 2003. – “Including Mechanisms in our Models of Ascriptive Inequality”, American Socio-logical Review, 68.
  • Revue Française de Sociologie, 2003. – “La théorie du choix rationnel. Les Foundations of social theory de James S. Coleman en débat”, 44, 2.
  • Rios D., 2004. – “Mechanistic Explanations in the Social Science”, Current Sociology, 52, 1.
  • Santoro M., 2003. – “Eventi e strutture : il positivismo narrativo di Andrew Abbott e l’eredità della scuola di Chicago”, Rassegna Italiana di Sociologia, 44, 4.
  • Sawyer R. K. 2003. – “Artificial Societies. Multiagent Systems and the Micro-Macro Link in Socio-logical Theory”, Sociological Methods and Research, 31, 3.
  • — 2004a. – “The Mechanisms of Emergence”, Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 34, 2.
  • — 2004b. – “Social Explanation and Computational Simulation », Philosophical Explorations, 7, 3.
  • Sawyer R. K. 2005. – Social Emergence. Societies as Complex Systems, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
  • Scheff T. J., 1992. – “Rationality and Emotion” in J. S. Coleman, T. Fararo, Rational Choice Theory: Advocacy and Critique, Newbury Park (Cal), Sage.
  • OnlineSchelling T. C., 1971. – “Dynamic Models of Segregation”, Journal of Mathematical Sociology, 1.
  • — 1998. – “Social Mechanisms and Social Dynamics” in P. Hedstrom, R. Swedberg (eds.), Social Mechanisms. An Analytical Approach to Social Theory, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
  • Schizzerotto A., 1997. – “Perché in Italia ci sono pochi diplomati e pochi laureati ? Vincoli strutturali e decisioni razionali degli attori come cause della contenuta espansione della scolarità superiore”, Polis, 11, 3.
  • Sichman J., Conte R., Gilbert N. (eds.) 1998. – Multi-Agent Systems and Agent Based Simulation, Berlin, Springer.
  • Simon A. H., Iwasaki Y., 1988. – “Causal Ordering, Comparative Static, and near Decomposability”, Journal of Econometrics, 39.
  • Snijders T., 1996. – “Stochastic Actor-Oriented Models for Network Change”, Journal of Mathematical Sociology, 21.
  • — 2001. – “The Statistical Evaluation of Social Network Dynamics”, Sociological Methodology, 31, pp. 361-395.
  • Snijders T., Van Duijn M. A. J., 1997. – “Simulation for Statistical Inference in Dynamic Network Models” in R. Conte, R. Hegselmann, P. Terna (eds.), Simulating Social Phenomena, Berlin, Springer.
  • Social Science Computer Review, 1988. – “Symposium on Computerized Simulation in the Social Sciences”, 6, 1.
  • Sociological Perspectives, 1995. – “Computer Simulations and Sociological Theory”, 38, 4.
  • Sociologie et Société, 2002. – “La théorie du choix rationnel contre les sciences sociales ? Bilan des débats contemporains”, 24, 1.
  • Sorensen A. G., 1977. – “The Structure of Inequality and the Processes of Attainment”, American Sociological Review, 42, 6.
  • — 1979. – “A Model and a Metric for the Analysis of the Intragenerational Status Attainment Process”, American Journal of Sociology, 85, 2.
  • — 1998. – “Theoretical Mechanisms and the Empirical Study of Social Processes” in P. Hedstrom, R. Swedberg (eds.), Social Mechanisms. An Analytical Approach to Social Theory, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
  • Stinchcombe A. L., 1991. – “The Condition of Fruitfulness of Theorizing about Mechanism in Social Science”, Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 21, 3.
  • Terna P., 1998. – “Simulation Tools for Social Scientists : Building Agent Based Models with SWARM”, Journal of Artificial Societies and Social Simulation, 1, 2.
  • The American Behavioral Scientist, 1965. – “Social Research with the Computer”, 8, 9.
  • — 1999. – “Computer Simulation in the Social Sciences”, 42, 10.
  • The Journal of Mathematical Sociology, 1990. – “Computer Simulation in Sociology”, 15, 2.
  • Troitzsch G. K., 1996. – “Computer Simulation and Social Sciences : On the Future of a Difficult Relation” in G. K. Troitzsch, U. Mueller, N. G. Gilbert, J. E. Doran (eds.), Social Science Microsimulation, Berlin, Springer.
  • — 1997. – “ Soc ial Scie nce Simulation – Or igins, Pros pects, Pur poses ” in R. C onte, R. Hegselmann, P. Terna (eds.), Simulating Social Phenomena, Berlin, Springer.
  • Troitzsch G. K., Mueller U., Gilbert N. G., Doran J. E., 1996. – Social Science Microsimulation, Springer, Berlin.
  • Udehn L., 2001. – Methodological Individualism. Background, History and Meaning, London, Routledge.
  • — 2002. – “The Changing Face of Methodological Individualism”, Annual Review of Sociology, 28.
  • Vallet L.-A., 2004. – “À propos d’un ouvrage peu connu dans la sociologie française : Making it Count. The improvement of social research and theory de Stanley Lieberson”, Revue Européenne de Sciences Sociales, 42, 129.
  • Van den Berg A., 1998. – “Is Sociological Theory too Grand for Social Mechanisms ?” in P. Hedstrom, R. Swedberg (eds.), Social Mechanisms: an Analytical Approach to Social Theory, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
  • Weber M., 1903-1906. – “Roscher et Knies e i problemi logici dell’economia politica di indirizzo storico” in P. Rossi, Saggi sul metodo delle scienze storico-sociali, Milano, Edizioni di comunità [Italian translation].
  • — [1904] 2000. – L’éthique protestante et l’esprit du capitalisme, French translation by I. Kalinowski, Paris, Flammarion.
  • — [1913] 1992. – “Essai sur quelques catégories de la sociologie compréhensive” in J. Freund, Essai sur la théorie de la science, Paris, Plon.
  • — [1917] 1992. – “Essai sur le sens de la ‘neutralité axiologique’ dans les sciences sociologiques et économiques” in J. Freund, Essai sur la théorie de la science, Paris, Plon.
  • — [1922] 1995. – Économie et société (vol. 1) in J. Chavy, É. de Dampierre (eds.), Paris, Plon.
  • Weisbuch G., 1992. – Complex Systems Dynamics, Redwood City, Addison Wesley.
  • Whicker M. L., Sigelman L., 1991. – Computer Simulation Applications: an Introduction, Newbury Park (Cal), Sage.
  • White H. C., 1970. – Chains of Opportunity. System Models of Mobility in Organizations, Cambridge, Harvard University Press.
  • Wippler R., 1978. – “The Structural-Individualist Approach in Dutch Sociology”, The Netherlands Journal of Sociology, 14.
  • — 1985. – “Explanatory Sociology : the Development of a Theoretically Oriented Research Program”, The Netherlands Journal of Sociology, 21, pp. 63-74.
  • Wunsch G., 1994. – “L’analyse causale en démographie” in R. Franck, Faut-il chercher aux causes une raison? L’explication causale dans les sciences humaines, Paris, Vrin, ch. 1.
  • Wu L. L., 2000. – “Some Comments on ‘Sequence Analysis and Optimal Matching Methods in Sociology’: Review and Prospect”, Sociological Methodology, 29, 1.
Gianluca Manzo
Université de Paris IV-Sorbonne – France Université de Trento – Italy
glmanzo@yahoo.fr
Uploaded on Cairn-int.info on 03/03/2014
Cite
Distribution électronique Cairn.info pour Ophrys © Ophrys. Tous droits réservés pour tous pays. Il est interdit, sauf accord préalable et écrit de l’éditeur, de reproduire (notamment par photocopie) partiellement ou totalement le présent article, de le stocker dans une banque de données ou de le communiquer au public sous quelque forme et de quelque manière que ce soit.
keyboard_arrow_up
Chargement
Loading... Please wait